Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T11:32:51.568Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Publishing, Belief, and Self-Trust

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2022

Alexandra Plakias*
Affiliation:
Hamilton College, New York, NY, USA

Abstract

This paper offers a defense of ‘publishing without belief’ (PWB) – the view that authors are not required to believe what they publish. I address objections to the view ranging from outright denial and advocacy of a belief norm for publication, to a modified version that allows for some cases of PWB but not others. I reject these modifications. In doing so, I offer both an alternative story about the motivations for PWB and a diagnosis of the disagreement over its permissibility. The original defense focused on consequentialist reasons for allowing PWB, offering mostly defensive arguments against potential criticisms. But I argue that once we shift our focus to the reasons why authors might be prone to PWB, we see a difference in two types of motivation: whereas I imagine PWB as arising from underconfident agents, critics point to cagey or nefarious authorial practices, or authors’ failure to clarify their own degrees of belief. Underlying the debate over norms of philosophical publishing, we find two different conceptions of philosophy itself.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bright, L.K. (2017). ‘On Fraud.’ Philosophical Studies 174(2), 291310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W. (Forthcoming). ‘The Belief Norm of Academic Publishing.’ Ergo.Google Scholar
Dang, H. and Bright, L.K. (2021). ‘Scientific Conclusions Need Not be Accurate, Justified, or Believed by Their Authors.’ Synthese 3–4, 117.Google ScholarPubMed
Fetterman, A., Curtis, S., Carre, J. and Sassenberg, K. (2019). ‘On the Willingness to Admit Wrongness: Validation of a New Measure and an Exploration of its Correlates.’ Personality and Individual Differences 138(1), 193202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleisher, W. (2020). ‘Publishing Without (Some) Belief.’ Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 9(4), 237–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habgood-Coote, J. (Forthcoming). ‘What's the Point of Authors?’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Jones, K. (2012). ‘The Politics of Intellectual Self-Trust.’ Social Epistemology 26(2), 237–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2005). ‘The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement.’ In Hawthorne, J. and Gendler, T. (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Volume 1, pp. 167–96. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kidd, I. (2016). ‘Intellectual Humility, Confidence, and Argumentation.’ Topoi 35, 395402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, J. (1999). ‘Testimonial Knowledge and Transmission.’ Philosophical Quarterly 49(197), 471–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, N. (2022). ‘In Trust We Trust.’ Social Epistemology 36(3), 283–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levy, N. (Forthcoming). Philosophy, Bullshit, and Peer Review. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Melnikoff, D. and Strohminger, N. (2020). ‘The Automatic Influence of Advocacy on Lawyers and Novices.’ Nature Human Behavior 4, 1258–64.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mills, C. (2005). “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology.’ Hypatia 20(3), 165–84.Google Scholar
Plakias, A. (2019). ‘Publishing Without Belief.’ Analysis 79(4), 638–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plakias, A. (2020). ‘Some Probably-Not-Very-Good Thoughts on Underconfidence.’ Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23(5), 861–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarıhan, I. (2022). ‘Problems with Publishing Philosophical Claims We Don't Believe.’ Episteme. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2021.56.Google Scholar