Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T04:28:30.996Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PROPOSITIONAL LEARNING: FROM IGNORANCE TO KNOWLEDGE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2018

Abstract

In this paper, I offer an account of propositional learning: namely, learning that p. I argue for what I call the “Three Transitions Thesis” or “TTT” according to which four states and three transitions between them characterize such learning. I later supplement the TTT to account for learning why p. In making my case, I discuss mathematical propositions such as Fermat's Last Theorem and the ABC Conjecture, and then generalize to other mathematical propositions and to non-mathematical propositions. I also discuss some interesting applications of the TTT, and reply to some noteworthy objections.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Aczel, A. 2007. Fermat's Last Theorem. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Alexander, P. A., Schallert, D. L. and Reynolds, R. E. 2009. ‘What Is Learning Anyway? A Topographical Perspective Considered.Educational Psychologist, 44: 176–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antognazza, M. R. 2015. ‘The Benefit to Philosophy of the Study of its History.’ British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23: 161–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. 2011. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, 3rd edition. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Castelvecchi, D. 2015. ‘The Impenetrable Proof.’ Nature, 526: 178–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Claveau, F. and Vergara Fernández, M. 2015. ‘Epistemic Contributions of Models: Conditions for Propositional Learning.’ Perspectives on Science, 23: 405–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, J. 1933. How We Think. Chicago, IL: Henry Regnery.Google Scholar
DeNicola, D. 2017. Understanding Ignorance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Driscoll, M. P. 2005. Psychology of Learning for Instruction. New York, NY: Pearson Education.Google Scholar
Dutant, J. 2015. ‘The Legend of the Justified True Belief Analysis.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 29: 95145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, H. 2000. Fermat's Last Theorem: A Genetic Introduction to Algebraic Number Theory. New York, NY: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Gettier, E. 1963. ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis, 23: 121–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. 2010. ‘The Myth of Factive Verbs.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80: 497522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2010. ‘Knowledge, Ignorance, and True Belief.’ Theoria, 76: 309–18.Google Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2011. ‘On Ignorance: A Reply to Peels.’ Philosophia, 39: 335–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2012. ‘On Ignorance: A Vindication of the Standard View.’ Philosophia, 40: 379–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2013. ‘Why the Standard Conception of Ignorance Prevails.’ Philosophia, 41: 239–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2015. ‘On the Ignorance, Knowledge, and Nature of Propositions.’ Synthese, 192: 3647–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2016. ‘Knowledge and Security.’ Philosophy, 91: 411–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Morvan, P. 2017. ‘Knowledge Before Gettier.’ British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 25: 1216–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masser, D. W. 1985. ‘Open Problems.’ In Chen, W. W. L. (ed.), Proceedings of the Symposium on Analytic Number Theory. London: Imperial College.Google Scholar
Mochizuki, S. 2017a. ‘Inter-universal Teichmüller Theory I: Construction of Hodge Theaters.’ http://www.kurims.kyoto-u.ac.jp/~motizuki/Inter-universal%20Teichmuller%20Theory%20I.pdf.Google Scholar
Mochizuki, S. 2017b. ‘Inter-universal Teichmüller Theory II: Hodge-Arakelov-theoretic Evaluation’ http://www.kurims.kyoto-u.ac.jp/~motizuki/Inter-universal%20Teichmuller%20Theory%20II.pdf.Google Scholar
Mochizuki, S. 2017c. ‘Inter-universal Teichmüller Theory III: Canonical Splittings of the Log-theta-lattice.’ http://www.kurims.kyoto-u.ac.jp/~motizuki/Inter-universal%20Teichmuller%20Theory%20III.pdf.Google Scholar
Mochizuki, S. 2017d. ‘Inter-universal Teichmüller Theory IV: Log-volume Computations and Set-theoretic Foundations.’ http://www.kurims.kyoto-u.ac.jp/~motizuki/Inter-universal%20Teichmuller%20Theory%20IV.pdf.Google Scholar
Noddings, N. 2016. Philosophy of Education, 4th edition. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Nola, R. and Irzik, G. 2005. Philosophy, Science, Education, and Culture. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Oesterlé, J. 1988. ‘Nouvelles approches du ‘théorème’ de Fermat.’ Astérisque, Séminaire Bourbaki, 694: 165–86.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1938. Experience and Prediction. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Singh, S. 2012. Fermat's Last Theorem. New York, NY: HarperCollins Publishers.Google Scholar
Stillwell, J. 2015. ‘What Does ‘Depth’ Mean in Mathematics?Philosophia Mathematica, 23: 215–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, R. and Wiles, A. 1995. ‘Ring Theoretic Properties of Certain Hecke Algebras.’ Annals of Mathematics, 141: 553–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. 2011. ‘Mythology of the Factive.Logos & Episteme, II: 143–52.Google Scholar
Wiles, A. 1995. ‘Modular Elliptic Curves and Fermat's Last Theorem.’ Annals of Mathematics, 141: 443551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar