Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-cjp7w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-26T20:11:26.487Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can Arbitrary Beliefs be Rational?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2022

Mattias Skipper*
Affiliation:
National University of Singapore, Singapore

Abstract

When a belief has been influenced, in part or whole, by factors that, by the believer's own lights, do not bear on the truth of the believed proposition, we can say that the belief has been, in a sense, arbitrarily formed. Can such beliefs ever be rational? It might seem obvious that they can't. After all, belief, supposedly, “aims at the truth.” But many epistemologists have come to think that certain kinds of arbitrary beliefs can, indeed, be rational. In this paper, I want to do two things. First, I want to show that the claim that arbitrary beliefs can be rational is inconsistent with the conjunction of two other attractive claims: one saying that rationality requires a certain kind of epistemic immodesty, and one saying that rationality forbids certain kinds of self-ascriptions of epistemic luck. Second, I want to evaluate different ways one might respond to this inconsistent triad. I won't defend any response in particular, but I'll draw out some notable costs and benefits of each response, which may help shed light on the question of whether arbitrary beliefs can be rational.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ballantyne, N. and Coffman, E. (2012). ‘Conciliationism and Uniqueness.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90, 657–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, L. (1980). ‘Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5, 5373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Builes, D., Horowitz, S. and Schoenfield, M. (2020). ‘Dilating and Contracting Arbitrarily.’ Noûs. Online first. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell-Moore, C. and Levinstein, B. (2021). ‘Strict Propriety is Weak.’ Analysis 81, 813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. (1984). ‘Justification and Truth.’ Philosophical Studies 110, 249–66.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. (2013). ‘A Defense of the (Almost) Equal Weight View.’ In Christensen, D. and Lackey, J. (eds), The Epistemology of Disagreement, pp. 98119. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dogramaci, S. and Horowitz, S. (2016). ‘An Argument for Uniqueness About Evidential Support.’ Philosophical Issues 26, 130–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. (ms.). ‘Lucky to Be Rational.’ Unpublished manuscript presented at the Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference 2008.Google Scholar
Elga, A. (2010). ‘Subjective Probabilities Should be Sharp.’ Philosophers’ Imprint 10, 111.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. (2007). ‘Reasonable Religious Disagreements.’ In Antony, L. (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods, pp. 194214. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1979). ‘What is Justified Belief?’ In Pappas, G. (ed.), Justification and Knowledge. Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Greaves, H. and Wallace, D. (2006). ‘Justifying Conditionalization: Conditionalization Maximizes Expected Epistemic Utility.’ Mind 115, 607–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, E. (2019). ‘A Defense of Intrapersonal Belief Permissivism.’ Episteme. Online first. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2019.19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. (1998). ‘A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.’ Philosophy of Science 65, 575603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. (2005). ‘How Probabilities Reflect Evidence.’ Philosophical Perspectives 19, 153–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2013). ‘Evidence can be Permissive.’ In Steup, M. and Turri, J. (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1985). ‘Imprecision and Indeterminacy in Probability Judgment.’ Philosophy of Science 52, 390409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1971). ‘Immodest Inductive Methods.’ Philosophy of Science 38, 5463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, H. (2018). ‘A Theory of Epistemic Supererogation.’ Erkenntnis 83, 349–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, H. (2019 a). ‘How Supererogation can Save Intrapersonal Permissivism.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 56, 171–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, H. (2019 b). ‘The Trouble With Having Standards.’ Philosophical Studies 176, 1225–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo-Wilson, C. and Wheeler, G. (2016). ‘Scoring Imprecise Credences: a Mildly Immodest Proposal.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93, 5578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meacham, C. (2013). ‘Impermissive Bayesianism.’ Erkenntnis 79, 11851217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (ms.). Epistemic Risk and the Demands of Rationality. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2011). ‘An Improper Introduction to Epistemic Utility Theory.’ In de Regt, H., Hartmann, S. and Okasha, S. (eds), Proceedings of EPSA: Amsterdam 09. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (Forthcoming). ‘Accuracy-first Epistemology Without Additivity.’ Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Podgorski, A. (2016). ‘Dynamic Permissivism.’ Philosophical Studies 173, 1923–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pryor, J. (2000). ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs 34, 517–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, G. (2001). ‘Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism.’ Philosophical Perspectives 15, 6991.Google Scholar
Schechter, J. (2013). ‘Rational Self-Doubt and the Failure of Closure.’ Philosophical Studies 163, 429–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schechter, J. (ms.). ‘Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga's ‘Lucky to Be Rational’.’ Presented at the Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference 2008.Google Scholar
Schoenfield, M. (2014). ‘Permission to Believe: Why Permissivism Is True and What It Tells Us About Irrelevant Influences on Belief.’ Noûs 48, 193218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoenfield, M. (2017). ‘The Accuracy and Rationality of Imprecise Credences.’ Noûs 51, 667–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoenfield, M. (Forthcoming). ‘Meditations of Beliefs Formed Arbitrarily.’ Oxford Studies in Epistemology.Google Scholar
Schultheis, G. (2018). ‘Living on the Edge: Against Epistemic Permissivism.’ Mind 127, 863–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seidenfeld, T., Schervish, M.L. and Kadane, J.B. (2012). ‘Forecasting with Imprecise Probabilities.’ International Journal of Approximate Reasoning 53, 1248–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. (2020). ‘Unacknowledged Permissivism.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 101, 158–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Titelbaum, M. and Kopec, M. (ms.). ‘Plausible Permissivism.’ Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Unger, P. (1968). ‘An Analysis of Factual Knowledge.’ Journal of Philosophy 65, 157–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1990). ‘Figures in a Probability Landscape.’ In Dunn, J. and Gupta, A. (eds), Truth or Consequences, pp. 345–56. Dodrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. (2005). ‘Epistemic Permissiveness.’ Philosophical Perspectives 19, 445–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. (2010). ‘You Just Believe That Because …Philosophical Perspectives 19, 445–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (2004). ‘Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78, 167212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ye, R. (2021). ‘The Arbitrariness Objection Against Permissivism.’ Episteme 18, 654–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (1994). ‘The Inescapability of Gettier Problems.’ Philosophical Quarterly 44, 6573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar