Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-pfhbr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T06:47:08.940Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy of Science circa 1950–2000: Some Things we (should have) Learned

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Harold I. Brown*
Affiliation:
Northern Illinois University, USA
*
Harold I. Brown, 541 N 7th Street, DeKalb, IL 60115, USA. Email: hibrown@niu.edu

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © ICPHS 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bahcall, J (1989) Neutrino Astrophysics. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
Brown, HI (1979) Perception, Theory, and Commitment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Brown, HI (2007) Conceptual Systems. Oxford/New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R (1956) Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In Carnap, Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 205221.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In Feigl, H, Maxwell, G (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science iii,. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 2897.Google Scholar
Franklin, A (2001) Are There Really Neutrinos? An Evidential History. Cambridge, MA: Perseus.Google Scholar
Goodman, N (1955) Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, ma: Harvard up.Google Scholar
Greenwood, J (1990) Two dogmas of neo-empiricism. Philosophy of Science 57: 553574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutting, G (2009) What Philosophers Know. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, NR (1958) Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
Hardwig, J (1991) The role of trust in knowledge. Journal of Philosophy 88: 693708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C (1945) Studies in the logic of confirmation. Mind 54: 126, 97121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaptchuk, T (1998) Intentional ignorance: a history of blind assessment and placebo controls in medicine. Bulletin of the History of Medicine 72: 389433.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhn, TS (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, TS (2000) The Road Since Structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, M (1958) Personal Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Price, HH (1940) The permanent significance of Hume's philosophy. Philosophy 15: 737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H (1962) The analytic and the synthetic. In Feigl, H, Maxwell, G (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science iii. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 358397Google Scholar
Quine, WV (1951) Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60: 2043.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W (1948) Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them. Philosophy of Science 15: 287315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W (1953a) Inference and meaning. Mind 62: 313338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W (1953b) Is there a synthetic a priori? Philosophy of Science 20: 121138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W (1954) Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science 21: 204228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toulmin, S (1961) Foresight and Understanding. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar