Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2xdlg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-20T03:38:35.448Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What Makes a Utopia Inconvenient? On the Advantages and Disadvantages of a Realist Orientation to Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 December 2016

BENJAMIN L. MCKEAN*
Affiliation:
Ohio State University
*
Benjamin L. McKean is Assistant Professor, Ohio State University2140 Derby Hall, 154 North Oval Mall, Columbus OH 43210 (mckean.41@osu.edu).

Abstract

Contemporary politics is often said to lack utopias. For prevailing understandings of the practical force of political theory, this looks like cause for celebration. As blueprints to apply to political practice, utopias invariably seem too strong or too weak. Through an immanent critique of political realism, I argue that utopian thought, and political theory generally, is better conceived as supplying an orientation to politics. Realists including Bernard Williams and Raymond Geuss explain how utopian programs like universal human rights poorly orient their adherents to politics, but the realists wrongly conclude that utopias and other ideal theories necessarily disorient us. As I show through an analysis of utopian claims made by Michel Foucault, Malcolm X, and John Rawls, utopias today can effectively disrupt entrenched forms of legitimation, foster new forms of political identity, and reveal new possibilities within existing institutions. Utopias are needed to understand the political choices we face today.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Afary, Janet, and Anderson, Kevin B. 2005. Foucault and the Iranian Revolution: Gender and the Seductions of Islamism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bavister-Gould, Alex. 2013. “Bernard Williams: Political Realism and the Limits of Legitimacy.” European Journal of Philosophy 21 (4): 593610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cabrera, Luis. 2010. The Practice of Global Citizenship. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciccariello-Maher, George. 2014. “Decolonial Realism: Ethics, Politics and Dialectics in Fanon and Dussel.” Contemporary Political Theory 13 (1): 222.Google Scholar
Dsouzinas, Costas, and Zizek, Slavoj, eds. 2010. The Idea of Communism. Brooklyn, NY: Verso.Google Scholar
Erman, Eva, and Möller, Niklas. 2015. “Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World: The Priority of Morality and the Autonomy of the Political.” British Journal of Political Science 45 (1): 215–33.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2011. “What Good Is It? Unrealistic Political Theory and the Value of Intellectual Work.” Analyze und Kritik 33 (2): 395416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flathman, Richard. 2010. “In and Out of the Ethical: The Realist Liberalism of Bernard Williams.” Contemporary Political Theory 9 (1): 7798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrester, Katrina. 2012. “Judith Shklar, Bernard Williams and Political Realism.” European Journal of Political Theory 11 (3): 247–72.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1997. Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth (Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Vol. 1), ed. Rabinow, Paul. New York: The New Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1998. Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, Vol. 2), ed. Faubion, James D.. New York: The New Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 2003. “Society Must Be Defended,” trans. Macey, David. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 2006. “Utopian Body.” In Sensorium: Embodied Experience, Technology, and Contemporary Art, ed. Jones, Caroline A., trans. Allais, Lucia. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 229–34.Google Scholar
Galston, William. 2010. “Realism in Political Theory.” European Journal of Political Theory 9 (4): 385411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2001. History and Illusion in Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2005. Outside Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2010a. Politics and the Imagination. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2010b. “Realismus, Wunschdenken, Utopie.” Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58 (3): 419–29.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2013. “Human Rights: A Very Bad Idea.” Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 60 (2): 83103.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2014. A World Without Why. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2015. “The Metaphysical Need and the Utopian Impulse.” In Actions, Reasons and Reason, eds. Stoecker, Ralf and Iorio, Marco (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2015), 14160.Google Scholar
Gledhill, James. 2012. “Rawls and Realism.” Social Theory and Practice 38 (1): 5582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golder, Ben. 2011. “Foucault's Critical (Yet Ambivalent) Affirmation: Three Figures of Rights.” Social & Legal Studies 20 (3): 283312.Google Scholar
Harris, Robert L. 2008. “Malcolm X: Human Rights and the United Nations.” In Malcolm X: A Historical Reader, eds. Conyers, James L. Jr. and Smallwood, Andrew P.. Durham, NC: Carolina Academic.Google Scholar
Honig, Bonnie, and Stears, Marc. 2011. “The New Realism: From modus vivendi to Justice,” Political Philosophy versus History? eds. Floyd, Jonathan and Stears, Marc. New York: Cambridge University Press, 177205.Google Scholar
Hutchings, Kimberly. 2011. “What is Orientation in Thinking? On the Question of Time and Timeliness in Cosmopolitical Thought.” Constellations 18 (2): 190204.Google Scholar
Ingram, James. 2013. Radical Cosmopolitics. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Jacoby, Russell. 2005. Picture Imperfect: Utopian Thought for an Anti-Utopian Age. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Jubb, Robert. 2015. “Playing Kant at the Court of King Arthur.” Political Studies 63 (4): 919–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1991. “What is Orientation in Thinking?” In Kant: Political Writings, 2nd enlarged edition, ed. Reiss, Hans. New York: Cambridge University Press, 237–49.Google Scholar
Kateb, George. 1972. Utopia and Its Enemies. New York: Schoken Books.Google Scholar
Keenan, Tom. 1987. “The ‘Paradox’ of Knowledge and Power: Reading Foucault on a Bias.” Political Theory 15 (1): 537.Google Scholar
Mantena, Karuna. 2012. “Another Realism: The Politics of Gandhian Nonviolence.” American Political Science Review 106 (2): 455–70.Google Scholar
Moyn, Samuel. 2010. The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Moyn, Samuel. 2014. “Human Rights in Heaven.” In Human Rights: Moral or Political? ed. Etinson, Adam. Forthcoming. Available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2432448.Google Scholar
Moyn, Samuel. 2015. “Human Rights and the Age of Inequality.” In Can Human Rights Bring Social Justice? eds. Lettinga, Doutje and van Troost, Lars. Amsterdam: Amnesty International Netherlands, 11–6.Google Scholar
Patton, Paul. 2004. “Power and Right in Nietzsche and Foucault.” International Studies in Philosophy 36 (3): 4361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paras, Eric. 2006. Foucault 2.0: Beyond Power and Knowledge. New York: Other Press.Google Scholar
Philp, Mark. 2012. “Realism without Illusions.” Political Theory 40 (5): 629–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2007. John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice, trans. Kosch, Michelle. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001a. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Kelly, Erin. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001b. The Law of Peoples; with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited.” Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2009. Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossi, Enzo, and Sleat, Matt. 2014. “Realism in Normative Political Theory.” Philosophy Compass 9 (10): 689701.Google Scholar
Roth, Kenneth. 2014. “The End of Human Rights?New York Review of Books, October 23, 2014. 61 (16) http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2014/oct/23/end-human-rights/.Google Scholar
Sargent, Lyman Tower. 2010. Utopianism: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shklar, Judith 1998. Political Thought and Political Thinkers, ed. Hoffmann, Stanley. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 2010. “Ideal and Nonideal Theory.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 38 (1): 536.Google Scholar
Smith, Curtis C. 1991. “Nkrumaism as Utopianism.” Utopian Studies 1 (3): 31–6.Google Scholar
Temkin, Moshik. 2012. “From Black Revolution to ‘Radical Humanism’: Malcolm X between Biography and International History.” Humanity 3 (2): 267–88.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, ed. Hawthorn, Geoffrey. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981. “Internal and External Reasons.” In Moral Luck. New York: Cambridge University Press, 101–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
X, Malcolm. 1990. Malcolm X Speaks, ed. Breitman, George. New York: Grove.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.