Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nmvwc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-26T20:42:50.219Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

American Political Thought and the American Revolution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

Louis Hartz
Affiliation:
Harvard University

Extract

“The great advantage of the American,” Tocqueville once wrote, “is that he has arrived at a state of democracy without having to endure a democratic revolution….” Fundamental as this insight is, we have not remembered Tocqueville for it, and the reason is rather difficult to explain. Perhaps it is because, fearing revolution in the present, we like to think of it in the past, and we are reluctant to concede that its romance has been missing from our lives. Perhaps it is because the plain evidence of the American revolution of 1776, especially the evidence of its social impact that our newer historians have collected, has made the comment of Tocqueville seem thoroughly enigmatic. But in the last analysis, of course, the question of its validity is a question of perspective. Tocqueville was writing with the great revolutions of Europe in mind, and from that point of view the outstanding thing about the American effort of 1776 was bound to be, not the freedom to which it led, but the established feudal structure it did not have to destroy. He was writing too, as no French liberal of the nineteenth century could fail to write, with the shattered hopes of the Enlightenment in mind. The American revolution had been one of the greatest of them all, a precedent constantly appealed to in 1793.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1952

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 de Tocqueville, Alexis, Democracy in America, ed. Bowen, F. (Boston, 1873), Vol. 2, p. 123Google Scholar.

2 Rededicating America (Indianapolis, 1920), p. 137Google Scholar.

3 In Blau, J. L. (ed.), Social Theories of Jacksonian Democracy (New York, 1947), p. 58Google Scholar.

4 “Dissertation on the Canon and Feudal Law,” in Adams, John, Works, ed. Adams, C. F. (Boston, 1856), Vol. 3, pp. 447465Google Scholar.

5 Quoted in Walther, D., Gouverneur Morris (New York and London, 1934), p. 76Google Scholar.

6 The term “feudal,” of course, has a technical reference to the medieval period. What Tocqueville and Adams largely had in mind, and what I refer to here, is the decadent feudalism of the later period—the “corporate” society of Europe, as some historians of the eighteenth century have put it. It has often been noted that the nonexistence of a feudal tradition—save for scattered remnants of which most, to be sure, were abolished by the American revolution—has been the great distinguishing feature of American civilization. But no interpretation of American politics or American political thought has as yet been inspired by this observation. It is obvious that the development of liberalism without feudalism, the development of Locke, as it were, without the antagonism of Filmer and Maistre, is bound to raise a whole series of peculiar problems. One of the reasons for our failure to examine these problems is undoubtedly to be found in the academic separation of American from European history. Any attempt to follow up the nonfeudal nature of the American experience requires the interchangeable use of American and European data and the formulation of issues that tend to be unfamiliar to the American specialist.

7 Adams, Samuel, Writings, ed. Cushing, F. H. (New York, 19041908), Vol. 2, p. 164Google Scholar.

8 Adams, John, Works, Vol. 4, p. 55Google Scholar.

9 Thornton, J. (ed.), The Pulpit of the American Revolution (Boston, 1876), pp. 196–7Google Scholar. The point I am making here about America in contrast to Europe is much the same point that Halevy makes about England in contrast to the Continent. We must not, of course, confuse French and English thought on this score. But the role of nonconformity in discouraging the rise of political religions was actually more marked in America than it was in England.

10 Quoted in Niles, H. (ed.), Principles and Acts of the Revolution in America (New York, 1876), p. 56Google Scholar.

11 Surveys Historic and Economic (London and New York, 1900), p. 406Google Scholar.

12 Cf. Einaudi, M., The Physiocratic Doctrine of Judicial Control (Cambridge, Mass., 1938)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Quoted in Adams, John, Works, Vol. 2, p. 522Google Scholar.

14 Jefferson, Thomas, Writings, ed. Ford, P. L. (New York, 18921899), Vol. 3, p. 231Google Scholar.

15 The Pulpit of the American Revolution, p. 311.

16 Dickinson, John, Writings, ed. Ford, P. L. (Philadelphia, 1895), p. 316Google Scholar.

17 Cf. Wright, B. F. Jr., “The Early History of Written Constitutions in America,” in Essays in History and Political Theory in Honor of Charles Howard McIlwain (Cambridge, Mass., 1936), pp. 344 ff.Google Scholar

18 Quoted in Shapiro, J., Condorcet and the Rise of Liberalism (New York, 1934), p. 223Google Scholar.

19 An American Dilemma (New York, 1944), p. 7Google Scholar.

20 Observations on the Importance of the American Revolution (London, 1785), p. 69Google Scholar.

21 Encyclopedia of Social Sciences (New York, 1937), Vol. 2, p. 645Google Scholar. By the same logic, we have never had a “Liberal Party” in the United States.

22 Democracy in America, Vol. 1, p. 58Google Scholar.

23 Sombart, W., Quintessence of Capitalism (London, 1915), p. 306Google Scholar.

24 Quoted in Parrington, V., Main Currents in American Thought (New York, 19271930), Vol. 1, p. 200Google Scholar.

25 The letter, dated 1778, is printed in Price's Observations, p. 95. For a general discussion of the problem, see Handlin, O. and Handlin, M., Commonwealth: Massachusetts (New York, 1947)Google Scholar, and Hartz, L., Economic Policy and Democratic Thought (Cambridge, Mass., 1948)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Some of the finest work on this subject is being done by Professor Carter Goodrich of Columbia. See his recent articles in the Political Science Quarterly.

27 Encyclopedia of Social Sciences, Vol. 15, p. 199Google Scholar.

28 de Crèrvecoeur, M. G. Jean, Letters from an American Farmer (London, 1926), p. 40Google Scholar.

29 Quoted in Principles and Acts of the Revolution in America, cited above (n. 8), p. 46.

30 Theory of Politics (New York, 1854), p. 262Google Scholar.

31 Nettels, C., Roots of American Civilization (New York, 1938), p. 315Google Scholar.

32 Quoted in Keller, A. G. (ed.), The Challenge of Facts and Other Essays (New Haven, 1914), p. 318Google Scholar.

33 Santayana, G., Character and Opinion in the United States (New York, 1924), p. 210Google Scholar.

34 Second Treatise on Civil Government (Oxford, 1947), p. 29Google Scholar.

35 The distinctive nature of these reforms is that they were a fulfillment of the past rather than, as in Europe, a revolt against it. The elimination of feudal vestiges in a society already under the dominion of liberalism is an entirely different matter from the introduction of liberalism in a society still heavily ridden by feudal forms. America's “social revolution” thus is not to be compared with the great social revolutions of Europe. I am reserving this general problem for another discussion.

36 Becker, C. L., Freedom and Responsibility in the American Way of Life (New York, 1945), p. 16Google Scholar.

37 I have sketched the main lines of this interpretation of Southern thought in The Reactionary Enlightenment: Southern Political Thought before the Civil War,” Western Political Quarterly, Vol. 5, pp. 3150 (March, 1952)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Note the words of Goethe:

Amerika, du hast es besser
Als unser Kontinent, das Alte
Hast keine verfallene Schloesser
Und keine Basalte.
Dich stoert nicht im Innern
Zu lebendiger Zeit
Unnuetzes Erinnern
Und vergeblicher Streit.

39 In The Challenge of Facts and Other Essays, p. 304. It will be seen that this analysis coincides to some extent with the much debated philosophy of Frederick Jackson Turner. The mistake of Turner was to miss the importance of the liberal ideas that the American settlers brought with them from the Old World and the East; nevertheless he seized upon an important truth when he emphasized the raw environment that they found. That feudalism could be established in Canada does not alter the fact that liberalism could be established much more easily in America because feudalism did not already exist. B. F. Wright, Jr., one of the earliest of the Turner critics, noted the significance of this factor of a new environment. Moreover, it cannot be denied that the abundance of land in America helped to support a system of liberal individualism by giving it a solid economic basis. Turner, in other words, seized upon a half-truth, and the argument over his theory has tended to obscure it. The American liberal community arose out of what must be accounted one of the happiest coincidences of modern history: the interplay between the philosophy of liberalism and an almost actualized state of nature. I am indebted to Mr. Rush Welter for originally suggesting to me that the interpretation of American thought advanced here, based on the nonexistence of a feudal tradition, might serve to confirm in part Turner's famous and controversial insight.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.