Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T04:41:55.083Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Homotopy Type Theory and the Vertical Unity of Concepts in Mathematics

from Part IV

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 July 2017

Elizabeth de Freitas
Affiliation:
Manchester Metropolitan University
Nathalie Sinclair
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Alf Coles
Affiliation:
University of Bristol
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baez, J. & Dolan, J. (2001). From finite sets to Feynman diagrams. In B. Engquist and W. Schmid (Eds.), Mathematics Unlimited – 2001 and Beyond, vol. 1, (pp. 29–50) Berlin: Springer. arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/math/0004133.Google Scholar
Borovik, A. (2005). What is it that makes a mathematician?, www.maths.manchester.ac.uk/avb/pdf/WhatIsIt.pdfGoogle Scholar
Chang, H. (2009). We have never been whiggish (about phlogiston), Centaurus, 51(4), 239264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corfield, D. (1997). Assaying Lakatos’s philosophy of mathematics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 28(1), 99121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corfield, D. (1998). Beyond the methodology of mathematics research programmes. Philosophia Mathematica, 6(3), 272301.Google Scholar
Corfield, D. (2001). The importance of mathematical onceptualisation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 32(3), 507533.Google Scholar
Corfield, D. (2003). Towards a philosophy ofreal mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corfield, D. (2015). Duality as a category-theoretic concept. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.07.004Google Scholar
Corfield, D. (forthcoming). Reviving the philosophy of geometry. In Landry, E. (Ed.), Categories for the working philosopher. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Harper, R. (2013). Computational trinitarianism. www.doc.ic.ac.uk/gds/PLMW/harper-plmw13-talk.pdfGoogle Scholar
Harris, M. (2008). Why mathematics you may ask? In Gowers, T. et al. (Eds.), Princeton companion to mathematics (pp. 966977). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Licata, D. & Shulman, M. (2013). Calculating the fundamental group of the circle in homotopy type theory. In LICS 2013: Proceedings of the Twenty-Eighth Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, pp. 223–232.Google Scholar
Lurie, J. (2009a). Higher Topos theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lurie, J. (2009b). Derived algebraic geometry V: Structured spaces, arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/0905.0459Google Scholar
Martin-Löf, P. (1984). Intuitionistic type theory. Napoli: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Schreiber, U. (2013). Differential cohomology in a cohesive-topos, arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/1310.7930.Google Scholar
Schreiber, U. (2014). Quantization via linear homotopy types, arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/1402.7041.Google Scholar
Schreiber, U. (forthcoming). Higher prequantum geometry. In G. Catren and M. Anel (Eds.), New spaces in mathematics and physics.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. (1987). Method in the philosophy of science and epistemology. In Nersessian, Nancy J. (Ed.), The process of science: Contemporary philosophical approaches to understanding scientific practice (pp. 1–39). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. (1989). Evolution and continuity in scientific change. Philosophy of Science, 56(3), 419437.Google Scholar
Shulman, M. (2015). Brouwer’s fixed-point theorem in real-cohesive homotopy type theory, arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/1509.07584.Google Scholar
Shulman, M. (forthcoming). Homotopy type theory: A synthetic approach to higher equalities. In Landry, E. (Ed.), Categories for the working philosopher. Oxford University Press. arXiv preprint: http://arxiv.org/abs/1601.05035.Google Scholar
Tappenden, J. (1995). Extending Knowledge and ‘Fruitful Concepts’: Fregean Themes in the Foundations of Mathematics. Nous, 29(4), 427467.Google Scholar
Univalent Foundations Program (2014). Homotopy type theory.Google Scholar
Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering significance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×