Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-68945f75b7-jtc8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-04T21:20:26.716Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - The Sign as Representation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 September 2012

Russell Daylight
Affiliation:
Charles Sturt University
Get access

Summary

We have so far considered Derrida's engagement with Saussure only in relation to linguistic signs, even if we have had to deliberate the inclusion or exclusion of writing. But the sign is more commonly understood as the basic unit of general semiology, or semiotics, rather than as a strictly linguistic object. Even Saussure, as a linguist, indicates that the linguistic sign is merely part, albeit the most important part, of a more inclusive science (Course: 68/101). And within this field of semiotics, or the science of signs, it is almost universally agreed that the sign conforms to the medieval maxim identified by Jakobson: aliquid stat pro aliquo, or, something that stands for something else. Steven Maras, for example, recently surveyed the semiotic landscape and found that:

From a basic starting point, semiotics can be described as the study of signs, and the sign described as an entity that ‘stands for’ something else. As Umberto Eco writes, ‘when – on the basis of an underlying rule – something actually presented to the perception of the addressee stands for something else, there is signification’ (Eco 1976: 8). Peirce defines the sign as ‘something which stands to somebody for something in some respect or capacity’ (Peirce 1965: 2.228). Articulated in this way, semiotics cannot be restricted to natural communication or systems of representation like speech or writing. As Chandler notes, ‘semiotics involves the study not only of what we refer to as ‘signs’ in everyday speech, but of anything which ‘stands for’ anything else’ (Chandler 2001: 1). Sless refers to the ‘stand-for’ relation as ‘ubiquitous’, and from a semiotic point of view ‘the basis of existence’ (Sless 1986: 3). (Maras 2002: 115)

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Edinburgh University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×