Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-68945f75b7-jtc8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-03T15:24:13.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Preference Satisfaction and Welfare

from Part II - Preferences, Welfare, and Normative Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Daniel M. Hausman
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
Get access

Summary

This chapter argues that the satisfaction of preferences – even when preferences are informed, rational, and generally spruced up – does not constitute well-being. Economists are mistaken when they make claims such as “Policy x is deemed better than policy y for an individual if and only if, given the opportunity, the individual would choose x over y” (Gul and Pesendorfer 2008, p. 24). In assessing preference-satisfaction theories of well-being, it is crucial to understand correctly what is meant by “preference.” For example, if preference were defined as a ranking in terms of expected benefit, then it would be true by definition that what individuals prefer would coincide with what they believed was good for them. If people’s expectations were correct, preference satisfaction would coincide with welfare. And if people choose what they prefer, then, as Gul and Pesendorfer maintain, they always choose what is best for them.

In the investigation of preference-satisfaction theories of welfare, I shall interpret preferences as economists do – that is, as total subjective comparative evaluations. There is no plausible alternative. The everyday sense of preferences as overall comparative evaluations is unsatisfactory for the purposes of a theory that identifies welfare and preference satisfaction, because it implies that when moral commitments conflict with preference, adhering to moral commitment always makes individuals worse off. Although doing what is right may not always be good for people, it should not always be bad for people whose preferences lead elsewhere. If one wants to define welfare in terms of preference, then one should take preferences to be total comparative evaluations.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×