Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-dwq4g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-26T00:20:43.465Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Convention and the regard to justice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Francis Snare
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Get access

Summary

Hume requires a theory of convention for two reasons. One is somewhat incidental to his defence of sentimentalism, but is relevant to the broader project of a naturalistic methodological individualism. Hume's approach, in this latter regard, is to explain social institutions (such as legal institutions or the marketplace) and social practices (such as promising or buying) in terms of social norms or rules (i.e., ‘convention’) which, in turn, he wants to explain in terms of acts and properties of individuals themselves plausibly susceptible of a naturalistic account. The second reason Hume needs a theory of convention is in order to give a naturalistic account of the special sort of sentiment which approves of just acts and persons. Hume needs, specifically, an account that can be used non-circularly in a sentimentalist account of our judgments of justice and injustice, i.e., for the judgments which are ‘hard cases’ for his theory.

Many philosophers have been concerned, in the context of philosophy of the social sciences or philosophy of language (that is, rather than in the context of moral philosophy) to propose theories of convention (or rules, or norms) within a general naturalist and methodologically individualist framework (e.g. Grice, 1957; Shwayder, 1965; Lewis, 1969; Blackburn, 1984, ch. 4). However, Hume attempts to produce a satisfactory theory of convention falling under a further constraint beyond what these philosophers require. His theory must also, must most of all, be adequate to meet Hume's second project as well, i.e., to defend his sentimentalism against the charge of circularity.

Type
Chapter
Information
Morals, Motivation, and Convention
Hume's Influential Doctrines
, pp. 283 - 309
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1991

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×