Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T13:24:51.085Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Passionate Thoughts: The Emotional Embodiment of Moral Concepts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 July 2009

Jesse J. Prinz
Affiliation:
University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, North Carolina, USA
Diane Pecher
Affiliation:
Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam
Rolf A. Zwaan
Affiliation:
Florida State University
Get access

Summary

In the 18th century, David Hume said that every idea is built up from copies of prior impressions. In modern terminology: all concepts are built up from stored records of perceptual states. This empiricist credo is enjoying a resurgence these days. Researchers in numerous fields are seriously investigating the hypothesis that thought has a perceptual basis. They are questioning the rationalist assumptions that have dominated cognitive science since its inception in the 1950s. Empiricism is still a fringe movement, however. It is often dismissed as gratuitously radical and utterly indefensible. That attitude has become something of a dogma, but it derives from two serious worries. One of them has to do with innate ideas. Empiricists have tended to be antinativists, and the current orthodoxy in cognitive science is to postulate a considerable amount of innate knowledge. I think the orthodoxy is mistaken, but I will have little to say about that here. The second major reason for rejecting empiricism has to do with abstract ideas. We often think about things that are far removed from sensory experience. There is no way to paint a mental picture of truth, justice, democracy, or necessity. If empiricism is to have any hope of success, it must be able to explain how we come to think about things at this level of abstraction.

I think the objection from abstract ideas must be dismantled piecemeal. There are different kinds of abstract ideas, and these must be accommodated in different ways.

Type
Chapter
Information
Grounding Cognition
The Role of Perception and Action in Memory, Language, and Thinking
, pp. 93 - 114
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adolphs, R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Cooper, G., & Damasio, A. R. (2000). A role for somatosensory cortices in the visual recognition of emotion as revealed by three-dimensional lesion mapping. Journal of Neuroscience 20, 2683–2690CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, S. W., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. (1999). Impairment of social and moral behaviour related to early damage in human prefrontal cortex. Nature Neuroscience 2, 1032–1037CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barsalou, L. W. (1987). The instability of graded structure: Implications for the nature of concepts. In U. Neisser (Ed.), Concepts and Conceptual Development: Ecological and Intellectual Factors in Categorization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22, 577–609Google ScholarPubMed
Blair, R. J. R., & Cipolotti, L. (2000). Impaired social response reversal – A case of “acquired sociopathy.”Brain 123, 1122–1141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chao, L. L., & Haxby, J. V., Martin, A. (1999). Attribute-based neural substrates in temporal cortex for perceiving and knowing about objects. Nature Neuroscience 2, 913–919CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chao, L. L., & Martin, A. (2000). Representation of manipulable manmade objects in the dorsal stream. NeuroImage 12, 478–484CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, R. M. (1959). Emotional reactions of rats to the pain of others. Journal of Comparative & Physiological Psychology 52: 132–134CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Critchley, H. D., Cornfield, D. R., Chandler, M. P., Mathias, C. J., & Dolan, R. J. (2000). Cerebral correlates of autonomic cardiovascular arousal: A functional neuroimaging investigation in humans. Journal of Physiology 523, 259–270CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Damasio, A. R. (1989). Time-locked multiregional retroactivation: A systems-level proposal for the neural substrates of recall and recognition. Cognition 33, 25–62CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes' Error: Emotion Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Gossett/Putnam
Damasio, A. R., Grabowski, T. J., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Ponto, L. L. B.Parvizi, J., & Hichwa, R. D. (2000). Subcortical and cortical brain activity during the feeling of self-generated emotions. Nature Neuroscience 3, 1049–1056CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ekman, P. (1972). Emotions in the Human Face. New York: Pergamon Press
Eisenberg, N. (2000). Emotion, regulation, and moral development. Annual Review of Psychology 51, 665–697CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J. A. (2004). Having concepts: A brief refutation of the twentieth century. Mind and Language
Fridlund, A. (1994). Human Facial Expression: An Evolutionary View. San Diego, CA: Academic Press
Frijda, N. H. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Gallese, V., Faddiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain 119, 593–609CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) does moral judgment work?Trends in Cognitive Science 6, 517–523CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293, 2105–2108CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (in preparation). Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason
Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and Moral Development: Implications for Caring and Justice. New York: Cambridge University Press
Hume, D. (1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature. P. H. Nidditch (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press
Jackendoff, R. (1992). Languages of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
James, W. (1884). What is an emotion?Mind 9, 188–205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press
Lange, C. G. (1885). Om sindsbevaegelser: et psyko-fysiologisk studie. Kjbenhavn: Jacob Lunds. Reprinted in The Emotions. C. G. Lange & W. James (Eds.), I. A. Haupt (Trans.) Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins Company, 1922
Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and Adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press
LeDoux J. E. (1996). The Emotional Brain. New York: Simon and Schuster
Martin, A., & Chao, L. L. (2001). Semantic memory and the brain: Structure and processes. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 11, 194–201CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McDowell J. (1985) Values and secondary qualities. In T. Honderich (Ed.), Morality and Objectivity: A Tribute to J. L. Mackie (pp. 110–129). London: Routledge
Millikan, R. G. (2000). On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay about Substance Concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Moll, J., Oliveira-Souza, R., Eslinger, P. J., Bramati, I. E, Mourao-Miranda, J., Andreiuolo, P., & Pessoa, L. (2002). The neural correlates of moral sensitivity: A functional magnetic resonance imaging investigation of basic and moral emotions. Journal of Neuroscience 22, 2730–2736CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Murphy, G. L., & Medin, D. L. (1985). The role of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological Review 92, 289–316CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R., & Barsalou, L. W. (2003). Verifying different-modality properties for concepts produces switching costs. Psychological Science 14, 119–124CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Prinz, J. J. (2002). Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Prinz, J. J. (2003). Imitation and moral development. In S. Hurley and N. Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on Imitation: From Cognitive Neuroscience to Social Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Prinz, J. J. (2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press
Prinz, J. J. (forthcoming). The emotional construction of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Roseman, I. J., Spindel, M. S., & Jose, P. E. (1990). Appraisals of emotion-eliciting events: Testing a theory of discrete emotions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59, 899–915CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. R. (1993). Disgust. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland, Handbook of Emotions. New York: Guilford Publications
Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality & Social Psychology 76, 574–586CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of morality (autonomy, community, divinity), and the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and Health. (pp. 119–169). New York: Routledge
Simmons, K., & Barsalou, L. W. (2003). The similarity-in-topography principle: Reconciling theories of conceptual deficits. Cognitive Neuropsychology 20, 451–486CrossRef
Simmons, W. K., Pecher, D., Hamann, S. B., Zeelenberg, R., & Barsalou, L. W. (2003). fMRI evidence for modality-specific processing of conceptual knowledge on six modalities. Meeting of the Society for Cognitive Neuroscience, New York, March
Spivey, M., Tyler, M., Richardson, D., & Young, E. (2000). Eye movements during comprehension of spoken scene descriptions. Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 487–492). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum
Warrington, E. K., & McCarthy, R. (1983). Category specific access dysphasia. Brain 106, 859–878CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wiggins, D. (1987). A sensible subjectivism. In Needs, Values, Truth. Oxford: Blackwell
Zajonc, R. B. (1984). On the primacy of affect. American Psychologist 39, 117–123CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×