Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T13:21:25.817Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Representative democracy and its critics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Nadia Urbinati
Affiliation:
Columbia University
Sonia Alonso
Affiliation:
Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung
John Keane
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Wolfgang Merkel
Affiliation:
Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung
Get access

Summary

The democracy of the moderns

The term ‘representative democracy’ conveys the complexity, richness and uniqueness of the political order of the moderns, an original synthesis of two distinct and in certain respects alternative political traditions. ‘Democracy’, a Greek word with no Latin equivalent, stands for direct rule (‘getting things done’) by the people. Representation, a Latin word with no Greek equivalent, entails a delegated action on the part of some on behalf of someone else. As a mixture of these two components, in its standard meaning representative democracy has four main features: (a) the sovereignty of the people expressed in the electoral appointment of the representatives; (b) representation as a free mandate relation; (c) electoral mechanisms to ensure some measure of responsiveness to the people by representatives who speak and act in their name; and (d) the universal franchise, which grounds representation on an important element of political equality. The central element of this standard account is that constituencies are formally defined by territory, not economic or corporate interests or cultural identities, an aspect that has belonged to democracy since Cleisthenes' reform of demes in Athens during the sixth century BCE: ‘in almost every democracy in the world, citizens are represented by where they live’ (Rehfeld 2005: 3). This basic formal equality in the distribution of voting power among adult citizens gives the mark of authorisation and legitimacy to a government that relies upon consent, yet not on the direct presence by the people in the lawmaking process.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Accarino, B. (1999) Rappresentanza. Bologna: Il Mulino.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R. (2002) Political representation. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Bailyn, B. (1992) The debate on the constitution: Federalist and antifederalist speeches, articles, and letters during the struggle over ratification, 2 vols. New York: The Library of America.Google Scholar
Barber, B. (1984) Strong democracy: Participatory politics for a new age. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bastid, P. (1939) Les discours de Sieyès dans les débats constitutionnels de l'An III (2 et 18 Thermidor). Édition critique avec une introduction et des notes, Paris: Hachette, pp. 58–9.Google Scholar
Bobbio, N. (1955) Politica e cultura. Turin: Einaudi.Google Scholar
Bobbio, N. (1999) Teoria generale della politica, ed. Bovero, M., Turin: Einaudi.Google Scholar
Böckenförde, E. W. (1991) State, society and liberty: Studies in political theory and constitutional law. New York and Oxford: Berg.Google Scholar
Bodin, J. (1992) On sovereignty: Four chapters from the six books of the Commonwealth, ed. Franklin, J.. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carré de Malberg, R. (1922) Contribution à la théorie générale de l'État, 2 vols. Paris: Librairie Recueil Sirey.Google Scholar
Clarke, M. V. (1964) Medieval representation and consent: A study of early parliaments in England and Ireland, with special reference to the modus tenendi parliamentum. New York: Russell & Russell.Google Scholar
Cochin, A. (1979) L'esprit du jacobinisme. Une interpretation sociologique de la révolution française. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
D'Holbach, P.-H., Baron, T. (1778–9) Représentants. In Encyclopédie; ou, Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, par une société de gens de lettres. Mis en ordre & publié par M. Diderot; & quant à la partie mathématique, par M. D'Alembert, 36 vols. Lausanne: Sociétés typographiques, 1781–82.Google Scholar
Dahl, R. A. (1971) Polyarchy: Participation and opposition. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, R. A. (2001) How democratic is the American constitution?New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Derathé, R. (1970) Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la science politique de son temps. Paris: Librairie Philosophique Vrin.Google Scholar
Doyle, W. (1987) ‘The parlements’, in Baker, K. M. (ed.) The French Revolution and the creation of modern political culture: vol. 1, The political culture of the old regime. Oxford: Pergamon Press, pp. 157–67.Google Scholar
Dunn, J. (1999) ‘Situating democratic political accountability’, in Przeworski, A., Stokes, S. C. and Manin, B. (eds.) Democracy, accountability, and representation. Cambridge University Press, pp. 329–44.Google Scholar
Dunn, J. (2005) Democracy: A history. New York: Atlantic Monthly Press.Google Scholar
Filmer, R. (1991) Patriarcha (1680), in Sommerville, J. P. (ed.) Patriarcha and other essays. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fralin, R. (1978) Rousseau and representation: A study of the development of his concept of political institutions. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Friedrich, C. J. (1963) Man and his government: An empirical theory of politics. New York: McGraw Book Company.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H. G. (2004) Truth and method. London, New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Gierke, O. (1958) Political theories of the middle age. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grotius, H. (1925) De jure belli ac pacis libri tres (1625), 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1996) Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1991) The metaphysics of morals (1785). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keane, J. (2009) The life and death of democracy. London: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1929) Vom Wesen und Wert der Demokratie. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1992) Introduction to the problems of legal theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1999) General theory of law and state. Union, NJ: The Lawbook Exchange.Google Scholar
Kishlansky, M. A. (1986) Parliamentary selection: Social and political choice in early modern England. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maffei, S. (1979) Il Consiglio politico finora inedito presentato al governo veneto nell'anno 1736. Venice: Palese.Google Scholar
Manin, B. (1997) The principles of representative government. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansbridge, J. J. (2003) ‘Rethinking representation’, American Political Science Review 97(4): 515–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maritain, J. (1943) Christianisme et démocratie. New York: Éditions de la Maison francaise.Google Scholar
Mayo, H. B. (1960) An introduction to democratic theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Michels, R. (1962) Political parties: A sociological study of the oligarchical tendencies of modern democracy. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Millar, F. (2002) The Roman Republic in political thought: The Menahem Stern Jerusalem Lectures. Hanover and London: University Press of New England.Google Scholar
Montesquieu, C. L.Baron, S. (1989) The spirit of the laws (1748). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mounier, J.-J. (1989) ‘Rapport du comité chargé du travail sur la constitution’, in Furet, F. and Halévie, R. (eds.) Orateurs de la révolution française, vol. 1. Les constituants. Paris: Pléiade.Google Scholar
Muirhead, R. (2006) ‘A defense of party spirit’, Perspectives on Politics 4: 713–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, J. (2008) ‘The original meaning of “democracy”: Capacity to do things, not majority rule’, Constellations 15(1): 3–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paine, T. (1989) The rights of man (1791–92), in Kuklick, B. (ed.) Political writings. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pennock, J. R. (1983) ‘Introduction’ in Pennock, J. R. and Chapman, J. W. (eds.), Liberal democracy. Nomos XXV. New York: NYU.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2003) ‘Deliberative democracy, the discursive dilemma, and republican theory’, in Fishkin, J. S. and Laslett, P. (eds.) Debating deliberative democracy. Malden: Blackwell, pp. 138–62.Google Scholar
Pitkin, H. (1967) The concept of representation. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993) Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rehfeld, A. (2005) The concept of constituency: Political representation, democratic legitimacy and institutional design. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Revel, J. (1987) ‘Les corps et communautés’, in Baker, K. M. (ed.) The French revolution and the creation of modern political culture: vol. 1, The political culture of the Old Regime. Oxford: Pergamon Press, pp. 225–42.Google Scholar
Rosanvallon, P. (1992) Le sacre du citoyen. Histoire du suffrage universel en France. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Rosanvallon, P. (1998) Le peuple introuvable. Histoire de la représentation démocratique en France. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Rosanvallon, P. (2006) La contre-démocratie. La politique à l'âge de la défiance. Paris: Editions du Seuil.Google Scholar
Rosenblum, N. (2008) On the side of the angels: An appreciation of parties and partisanship. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rousseau, J.-J. (1985) The government of Poland (1772). Indianapolis: Hackett, pp. 36–7.Google Scholar
Rousseau, J.-J. (1987) On the social contract or principles of political rights (1762), in Basic political writings. Indianapolis: Hackett, pp. 139–227.Google Scholar
Schmitt, C. (1928) Constitutional theory (2008 edn.) Durham and London: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J. (1962) Capitalism, socialism, and democracy (1942). New York: Harper Torchbook.Google Scholar
Sieyès, E.-J. (1985) Ėcrits politiques. Paris: Editions des archives contemporaines.Google Scholar
Sieyès, E.-J. (1998) ‘Bases de l'ordre social’, in Pasquino, P., Sieyes et l'invention de la constitution en France. Paris: Odile Jacob.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. (2002) ‘Hobbes and the purely artificial person of the state’, in Visions of Politics. 3 vols. Vol. 3. Cambridge University Press, pp. 177–208.Google Scholar
Thompson, D. F. (1987) Political ethics and public office. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Urbinati, N. (1998) ‘Democracy and populism’, Constellations 5(1): 110–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urbinati, N. (2005) ‘Continuity and rupture: Political judgment in democratic representation’, Constellations 12(1): 194–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urbinati, N. (2006) Representative democracy: Principles and genealogy. University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urbinati, N. and Warren, M. (2008) ‘The concept of representation in contemporary democracy’, The Annual Review of Political Science 11: 387–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaughan, C. E. (1962) The political writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 2 vols. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Wood, A. G. (1969) The creation of the American revolution, 1776–1787. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. (1997) ‘Deferring group representation’, in Shapiro, I. and Kymlicka, W. (eds.) Ethnicity and group rights. Nomos XXXIX. New York University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×