Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-sjtt6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-27T20:07:24.515Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Canetti and Nietzsche: An Introduction to Masse und Macht

from Philosophy and Social Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 April 2017

Ritchie Robertson
Affiliation:
German language and literature at St. John's College, Oxford
Irene Stocksiecker Di Maio
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of German at Louisiana State University and A & M College
William Collins Donahue
Affiliation:
Duke University
Anne Fuchs
Affiliation:
Professor of modern German literature and culture at University College Dublin.
Helga W. Kraft
Affiliation:
Professor and Head of the Department of Germanic Studies at the University of Illinois at Chicago.
Wolfgang Mieder
Affiliation:
University of Vermont, Department of German and Russian
Harriet Murphy
Affiliation:
Department of German Studies, University of Warwick, Coventry, England
Johannes Pankau
Affiliation:
Carl von Ossietzky Universität Oldenburg
Julian Preece
Affiliation:
University of Kent, Canterbury, UK
Ritchie Robertson
Affiliation:
Professor of German and a Fellow of St. John's College at the University of Oxford.
Sigurd Paul Scheichl
Affiliation:
University Innsbruck
Dagmar C.G. Lorenz
Affiliation:
Dagmar C. G. Lorenz is Professor of German at the University of Illinois, Chicago
Get access

Summary

Masse und Machtis a study of human nature and human society in the tradition of Darwinian naturalism that runs, by way of Nietzsche and Freud, down to the sociobiological literature of our own day. “Naturalism” here is not a literary but a philosophical term. It implies the attempt to study human life as part of nature, with the help of the natural sciences, and without reference to any non-natural or supernatural concepts such as divine revelation, a God-given order, or Platonic forms. Darwinian naturalism is a grandiose attempt, in Nietzsche's words, to translate man back into nature, to remove the idealistic scribblings that had disfigured the original text “homo natura.”

Darwin's name provides a convenient label, or emblem, for this project, but he did not initiate it. In the seventeenth century, Thomas Hobbes constructed an anthropology, or an account of humanity, based ultimately on scientific materialism, in which nature usurped the place of God. The Enlightenment tried to devise a more optimistic anthropology, in which man's natural desires and drives were declared good. The theory of evolution set out in The Origin of Species (1859) and explicitly applied to humanity in The Descent of Man (1871), though contested in its time, eventually pulled together many previous explorations of man's place within the natural world and confirmed that man was to be understood not as divinely created but as a special kind of animal. “We no longer derive man from ‘spirit,’ from ‘divinity,’ we have put him back among the animals,” wrote Nietzsche.Once convinced that man had evolved from animals, subsequent thinkers could speculate about how modern social institutions and moral standards had developed from equivalents in human prehistory, and these in turn from analogues to be observed in the social life of animals. Among such speculations, Nietzsche's Zur Genealogie der Moral (1888, The Genealogy of Morals) is a particularly radical attempt to explain how man became an animal that could make and keep promises, distinguish the morally “evil” from the merely “bad,” and develop the ascetic ideals that were the foundation of culture; while Freud in Totem und Tabu (1913, Totem and Taboo, 1919) undertook to derive the institutions of society, art, and religion from the Oedipus complex as supposedly embodied in the social life of early man. Both are indebted to evolutionary thought, though neither Nietzsche nor Freud accepted Darwin's particular version of evolution.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Boydell & Brewer
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×