Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Print publication year: 2008
  • Online publication date: June 2012

Part II - Conceptual Foundations

  • Edited by Philip Robbins, Washington University, St Louis, Murat Aydede, University of Florida
  • Publisher: Cambridge University Press
  • pp 53-182

References

Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43–64.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (in press). Defending the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Ballard, D., Hayhoe, M. M., Pook, P. K., & Rao, R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 723–767.
Bingham, G. (1988). Task-specific devices and the perceptual bottleneck. Human Movement Science, 7, 225–264.
Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 268–305). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brooks, R. A. (1991a). Intelligence without reason. In J. Myopoulos & R. Reiter (Eds.), Proceedings of the 12th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-91) (pp. 569–595). San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
Brooks, R. A. (1991b). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–160. (Modified version reprinted in J. Haugeland [Ed.], Mind design II: Philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence [pp. 395–420]. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.)
Brooks, R. A. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: The early history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. In P. French, T. Uehling Jr., & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy (Vol. 4, pp. 73–121). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Burge, T. (1986a). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95, 3–45.
Burge, T. (1986b). Intellectual norms and foundations of mind. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 697–720.
Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cognitive science and parallel distributed processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1998). Magic words: How language augments human computation. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162–183). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (2005a). Beyond the flesh: Some lessons from a mole cricket. Artificial Life, 11, 233–244.
Clark, A. (2005b). Word, niche and super-niche: How language makes minds matter more. Theoria, 20, 255–268.
Clark, A. (2007). Re-inventing ourselves: The plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(3), 263–282.
Clark, A. (in press). Coupling, constitution and the cognitive kind: A reply to Adams and Aizawa. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 10–23.
Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1978). Where am I? In D. C. Dennett (Ed.), Brainstorms (pp. 311–323). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press.
Ebbs, G. (1998). Rule-following and realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Egan, F. (1992). Individualism, computation, and perceptual content. Mind, 101, 443–459.
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1982). Cognitive science and the twin-earth problem. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23, 98–118.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fowler, C., & Turvey, M. T. (1978). Skill acquisition: An event approach with special reference to searching for the optimum of a function of several variables. In G. Stelmach (Ed.), Information processing in motor control and learning (pp. 1–40). New York: Academic Press.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
Goody, J. (1977). The domestication of the savage mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gray, W. D., & Fu, W.-T. (2004). Soft constraints in interactive behavior: The case of ignoring perfect knowledge in-the-world for imperfect knowledge in-the-head. Cognitive Science, 28, 359–382.
Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Reprinted from Acta Philosophica Fennica, 58, [1995], 233–267.)
Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Loar, B. (1988). Social content and psychological content. In R. Grimm & D. Merrill (Eds.), Contents of thought (pp. 99–110). Tucson: University of Arizona Press.
Newell, A. (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cognitive Science, 4, 135–183.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1976). Computer science as empirical enquiry. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design (pp. 35–66). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Norman, D. (1993). Cognition in the head and in the world. Cognitive Science, 17, 1–6.
Odling-Smee, J., Laland, K., & Feldman, M. (2003). Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information (2nd ed.). Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2000.
Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (Eds.). (2001). Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pettit, P. (1993). The common mind: An essay on psychology, society, and politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning.” In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind and knowledge (pp. 131–193). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rogers, Y., & Scaife, M. (1997). Distributed cognition. Retrieved May 13, 2008, from http://www.irit.fr/ACTIVITES/GRIC/cotcos/pjs/TheoreticalApproaches/DistributedCog/DistCognitionpaperRogers.htm.
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.
Rupert, R. (in press). Representation in extended cognitive systems: Does the scaffolding of language extend the mind? In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Salzman, E., & Kelso, J. A. S. (1987). Skilled actions: A task dynamic approach. Psychological Review, 94, 84–106.
Savage-Rumbaugh, S., & Lewin, R. (1994). Kanzi: The ape at the brink of the human mind. New York: Wiley and Sons.
Savage-Rumbaugh, S., Shanker, S. G., & Taylor, T. J. (1998). Apes, language, and the human mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
Scaife, M., & Rogers, Y. (1996). External cognition: How do graphical representations work? International Journal of Human-Computer Studies, 45, 185–213.
Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–424.
Segal, G. (1989). Seeing what is not there. Philosophical Review, 98, 189–214.
Shapiro, L. (1997). A clearer vision. Philosophy of Science, 64, 131–153.
Stenning, K., & Oberlander, J. (1995). A cognitive theory of graphical and linguistic reasoning: Logic and implementation. Cognitive Science, 19, 97–140.
Turner, J. S. (2000). The extended organism: The physiology of animal-built structures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (1994). Wide computationalism. Mind, 101, 351–372.
Wilson, R. A. (1995). Cartesian psychology and physical minds: Individualism and the sciences of the mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Misrepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 31–52). New York: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (2003). Individualism. In S. Stich & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to philosophy of mind (pp. 256–287). New York: Blackwell.
Wilson, R. A. (2004a). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences: Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (2004b). Recent work in individualism in the social, behavioural and biological sciences. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 397–423.
Wilson, R. A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life: The individual in the fragile sciences: Biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, R. A. (unpublished). Meaning making and the mind of the externalist.
Zhang, J., & Norman, D. A. (1994). Representations in distributed cognitive tasks. Cognitive Science, 18, 87–122.

References

Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43–64.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (in press). Defending the bounds of cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Aizawa, K. (2007). Understanding the embodiment of perception. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 5–25.
Aizawa, K., & Adams, F. (2005). Defending non-derived content. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 661–669.
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. New York: Ballantine Books.
Block, N. (2005). Review of Alva Noë's Action in perception. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259–272.
Brooks, R. (1997). Intelligence without representation. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design II (pp. 121–145). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots, and the extended mind. Mind & Language, 16, 121–145.
Clark, A. (2002). Towards a science of the bio-technological mind. International Journal of Cognition and Technology, 1, 21–33.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind. Analysis, 65, 1–11.
Clark, A. (in press). Memento's revenge: The extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.
Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds. New York: Basic Books.
Dennett, D. C. (2000). Making tools for thinking. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 17–29). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gibbs, R. J. (2001). Intentions as emergent products of social interactions. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and intentionality (pp. 105–122). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having thought (pp. 207–237). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hurley, S. L. (1998). Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58, 1–6.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.
McClamrock, R. (1995). Existential cognition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O’Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the “real” mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46, 461–488.
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press.
Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.
Rupert, R. (in press). Representation in extended cognitive systems: Does the scaffolding of language extend the mind? In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Schlatter, M., & Aizawa, K. (2008). Walter Pitts and “A logical calculus.” Synthese, 162, 232–250.
Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artifacts, and the extended mind (pp. 239–254). In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Susi, T., Lindblom, J., & Ziemke, T. (2003). Beyond the bounds of cognition. In K. Forbus, D. Gentner, & T. Regier (Eds.), Proceedings of the 25th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1305–1310). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Sutton, J. (2005). Memory and the extended mind: Embodiment, cognition, and culture. Cognitive Processing, 6(4), 223–226.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamical systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91, 345–381.
Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 625–636.
Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

References

Ariew, A. (1999). Innateness is canalization. In V. Hardcastle (Ed.), Biology meets psychology: Conjectures, connections, constraints (pp. 117–138). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bahrick, H. P. (1979). Maintenance of knowledge: Questions about memory we forgot to ask. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 108, 296–308.
Bahrick, H. P. (1984). Semantic memory content in permastore: Fifty years of memory for Spanish learned in school. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 1–29.
Ballard, D. H., Hayhoe, M. M., Pook, P. K., & Rao, R. P. N. (1997). Deictic codes for the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 723–742.
Block, N. (1981). Introduction: What is innateness? In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 279–281). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bloom, P. (2000). How children learn the meanings of words. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.
Butler, K. L. (1998). Internal affairs: Making room for psychosemantic internalism. Boston: Kluwer.
Carey, S. (1995). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Churchland, P. S., Ramachandran, V., & Sejnowski, T. (1994). A critique of pure vision. In C. Koch & J. Davis (Eds.), Large-scale neuronal theories of the brain (pp. 23–60). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, cognitive science and parallel distributed processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1995). Moving minds: Situating content in the service of real-time success. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives: Vol. 9. AI, connectionism, and philosophical psychology (pp. 89–104). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1998). Magic words: How language augments human computation. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory, and the extended mind. Analysis, 65, 1–11.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.
Clark, A., & Thornton, C. (1997). Trading spaces: Computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 57–66.
Cowie, F. (1999). What's within? Nativism reconsidered. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of minds: Toward an understanding of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.
Dretske, F. (1998). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Elman, J., Bates, E., Johnson, M., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Representations (pp. 257–316). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J. (2003). Hume variations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Goldin-Meadow, S., & Zheng, M. (1998). Thought before language: The expression of motion events prior to the impact of a conventional language model. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes (pp. 26–54). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Griffiths, P. (2002). What is innateness? Monist, 85, 70–85.
Griffiths, P., & Gray, R. (2004). The developmental systems perspective: Organism-environment systems as units of development and evolution. In K. Preston & M. Pigliucci (Eds.), Phenotypic integration: Studying the ecology and evolution of complex phenotypes (pp. 409–431). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind grows: A developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese, 122, 29–51.
Grush, R. (1997). The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology, 10, 5–23.
Haugeland, J. (1995). Mind embodied and embedded. In Y. Houng & J. Ho (Eds.), Mind and cognition (pp. 3–37). Taipei, Taiwan: Institute of European and American Studies, Academia Sinica.
Houghton, D. (1997). Mental content and external representations. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 159–177.
Hurley, S. (1998). Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58, 1–6.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Keil, F. (1990). Constraints on constraints: Surveying the epigenetic landscape. Cognitive Science, 14, 135–168.
Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. Mind & Language, 13, 347–369.
Markman, E. (1989). Categorization and naming in children: Problems of induction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
McClamrock, R. (1995). Existential cognition: Computational minds in the world. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
McGinn, C. (1989). Mental content. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O’Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the “real” mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46, 461–488.
Prinz, J. (2000). The duality of content. Philosophical Studies, 100, 1–34.
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rupert, R. (1996). The best test theory of extension. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois at Chicago.
Rupert, R. (1998). On the relationship between naturalistic semantics and individuation criteria for terms in a language of thought. Synthese, 117, 95–131.
Rupert, R. (1999). The best test theory of extension: First principle(s). Mind & Language, 14, 321–355.
Rupert, R. (2001). Coining terms in the language of thought: Innateness, emergence, and the lot of Cummins's argument against the causal theory of mental content. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 499–530.
Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.
Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind & Language, 17, 233–265.
Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge: New studies on cognition and intentionality (pp. 239–254). Berlin: de Gruyter.
Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Treisman, A. (1998). The perception of features and objects. In R. D. Wright (Ed.), Visual attention (pp. 26–54). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wilson, R. (1999). The individual in biology and psychology. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays (pp. 357–374). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wimsatt,W.(1999). Generativity,entrenchment, evolution, and innateness: Philosophy, evolutionary biology, and conceptual foundations of science. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays (pp. 139–179). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

References

Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.
Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing. Synthese, 101, 401–431.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief (pp. 17–36). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dretske, F. (1990). Reply to reviewers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1(4), 819–839.
Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational genera. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & J. Garron (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61–89). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lloyd, D. (1989). Simple minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
McGinn, C. (1982). The structure of content. In A. Woodfield (Ed.), Thought and object (pp. 207–258). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McGinn, C. (1989). Mental content. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. (1989/1993). Biosemantics. In R. Millikan (Ed.), White queen psychology and other essays for Alice (pp. 83–101). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Reprinted from Journal of Philosophy, 86, 281–297.)
Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 939–973.
O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2002). What it is like to see: A sensorimotor theory of perceptual experience. Synthese, 79, 79–103.
Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. London: Acumen.
Rowlands, M. (2006). Body language: Representation in action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Skarda, C., & Freeman, W. (1987). How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 161–195.
Smithers, T. (1994). Why better robots make it harder. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J. Meyer, & S. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to animats 3 (pp. 64–72). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91, 345–381.
Webb, B. (1994). Robotic experiments in cricket phonotaxis. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J. Meyer, & S. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to animats 3 (pp. 45–54). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wheeler, M. (1994). From activation to activity. Artificial Intelligence and the Simulation of Behaviour Quarterly, 87, 36–42.
Wilson, R. (1995). Cartesian psychology and physical minds: Individualism and the sciences of the mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.

References

Abraham, F. D., Abraham, R., & Shaw, C. D. (1991). A visual introduction to dynamical systems for psychology. Santa Cruz, CA: Aerial Press.
Adolphs, R., Bechara, A., Tranel, D., Damasio, H., & Damasio, A. R. (1995). Neuropsychological approaches to reasoning and decision-making. In A. R. Damasio, H. Damasio, & Y. Christen (Eds.), Neurobiology of decision-making (pp. 157–80). New York: Springer-Verlag.
Ballard, D. H. (1991). Animate vision. Artificial Intelligence, 48, 57–86.
Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22, 295–318.
Bechtel, W., & Graham, G. (Eds.). (1999). A companion to cognitive science. London: Blackwell.
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Busemeyer, J. R., & Townsend, J. T. (1993). Decision field theory: A dynamic-cognitive approach to decision making in an uncertain environment. Psychological Review, 100(3), 432–459.
Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (2002). The extended mind. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 643–652). New York: Oxford University Press. (Reprinted from Analysis, 58, 10–23.)
Conklin, J., & Eliasmith, C. (2005). An attractor network model of path integration in the rat. Journal of Computational Neuroscience, 18, 183–203.
Eliasmith, C. (1996). The third contender: A critical examination of the dynamicist theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 9(4), 441–463.
Eliasmith, C. (2000). Is the brain analog or digital? The solution and its consequences for cognitive science. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 1(2), 147–170.
Eliasmith, C. (2001). Attractive and in-discrete: A critique of two putative virtues of the dynamicist theory of mind. Minds and Machines, 11, 417–426.
Eliasmith, C. (2003). Moving beyond metaphors: Understanding the mind for what it is. Journal of Philosophy, 100(10), 493–520.
Eliasmith, C. (2004). Learning context sensitive logical inference in a neurobiological simulation. In S. Levy & R. Gayler (Eds.), AAAI Fall Symposium: Compositional Connectionism in Cognitive Science (pp. 17–20). Menlo Park, CA: Association for the Advancement of Artificial Intelligence Press.
Eliasmith, C. (2005a). Cognition with neurons: A large-scale, biologically realistic model of the Wason task. In G. Bara, L. Barsalou, & M. Bucciarelli (Eds.), Proceedings of the 27th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Eliasmith, C. (2005b). A unified approach to building and controlling spiking attractor networks. Neural Computation, 17(6), 1276–1314.
Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Eliasmith, C., & Thagard, P. (2001). Integrating structure and meaning: A distributed model of analogical mapping. Cognitive Science, 25(2), 245–286.
Eliasmith, C., Westover, M. B., & Anderson, C. H. (2002). A general framework for neurobiological modeling: An application to the vestibular system. Neurocomputing, 46, 1071–1076.
Elman, J. L. (1991). Distributed representations, simple recurrent networks, and grammatical structure. In D. Touretzky (Ed.), Connectionist approaches to language learning (pp. 91–122). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.
Finger, S. (2000). The minds behind the brain: A history of the pioneers and their discoveries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.
Freudenthal, H. (1970–1990). Norbert Weiner. In C. C. Gillespie (Ed.), Dictionary of scientific biography. New York: Scribner's.
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gibson, J. J., & Gibson, E. J. (1955). Perceptual learning: Differentiation or enrichment? Psychological Review, 62, 324–341.
Gorman, R. P., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1988). Analysis of hidden units in a layered network trained to classify sonar targets. Neural Networks, 1, 75–89.
Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–544.
Holroyd, C., & Coles, M. (2002). The neural basis of human error processing: Reinforcement learning, dopamine, and the error-related negativity. Psychological Review, 109, 679–709.
Hubel, D., & Wiesel, T. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat's visual cortex. Journal of Physiology (London), 160, 106–154.
Hull, C. (1935). The conflicting psychologies of learning – a way out. Psychological Review, 42, 491–516.
Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language: Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kanerva, P. (1994). The spatter code for encoding concepts at many levels. In M. Marinaro & P. G. Morasso (Eds.), Proceedings of the International Conference on Artificial Neural Networks (Vol. 1, pp. 226–229). Sorrento, Italy: Springer-Verlag.
Lockery, S., Fang, Y., & Sejnowski, T. (1990). A dynamical neural network model of sensorimotor transformation in the leech. Neural Computation, 2, 274–282.
Miller, P., Brody, C. D., Romo, R., & Wang, X. J. (2003). A recurrent network model of somatosensory parametric working memory in the prefrontal cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 13, 1208–1218.
Mindell, D. (1995). Engineers, psychologists, and administrators: Wartime control systems research, 1941–1945. IEEE Control Systems Magazine, 15(4), 91–99.
Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (1994). A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection. Psychological Review, 101(4), 608–631.
Parsons, L., & Osherson, D. (2001). New evidence for distinct right and left brain systems for deductive versus probabilistic reasoning. Cerebral Cortex, 11, 954–965.
Parsons, L., Osherson, D., & Martinez, M. (1999). Distinct neural mechanisms for propositional logic and probabilistic reasoning. Paper presented at the 40th Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society, Dallas, TX.
Plate, A. (1991). Holographic reduced representations: Convolution algebra for compositional distributed representations. In Proceedings of the 12th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 30–35). San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
Plaut, D. C., & McClelland, J. L. (1993). Generalization with componential attractors: Word and nonword reading in an attractor network. In Proceedings of the 15th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 824–829). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Port, R., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rieke, F., Warland, D., de Ruyter van Steveninick, R., & Bialek, W. (1997). Spikes: Exploring the neural code. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Robertson, S. S., Cohen, A. H., & Mayer-Kress, G. (1993). Behavioural chaos: Beyond the metaphor. In L. B. Smith & E. Thelen (Eds.), A dynamic systems approach to development: Applications (pp. 120–150). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). On learning the past tenses of English verbs. In J. L. McClelland & D. E. Rumelhart (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 216–271). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sejnowski, T. J., & Rosenberg, C. R. (1986). Nettalk: A parallel network that learns to read aloud. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 14, 179–211.
Seung, H. S. (1996). How the brain keeps the eyes still. In Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 93, 13339–13344.
Smolensky, P. (1990). Tensor product variable binding and the representation of symbolic structures in connectionist systems. Artificial Intelligence, 46, 159–217.
Sperber, D., Cara, E., & Girotto, R. (1995). Relevance theory explains the selection task. Cognition, 57, 31–95.
Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Thagard, P. (1996). Mind: Introduction to cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91(7), 345–381.
van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(5), 615–665.
van Gelder, T. (1999) Dynamic approaches to cognition. In R. Wilson & F. Keil (Eds.), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences (pp. 244–246). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wason, P. C. (1966). Reasoning. In B. M. Foss (Ed.), New horizons in psychology (pp. 131–151). Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158–177.
Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics: Or the control and communication in the animal and the machine. New York: John Wiley.
Wiesel, T. N., & Hubel, D. H. (1963). Effects of visual deprivation on morphology and physiology of cells in the cat's lateral geniculate body. Journal of Neurophysiology, 26, 978–993.
Zhang, K. (1996). Representation of spatial orientation by the intrinsic dynamics of the head-direction cell ensemble: A theory. Journal of Neuroscience, 16, 2112–2126.

References

Agre, P. E. (1995). Computational research on interaction and agency. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 1–52.
Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system and its control processes. In K. W. Spence & J. T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 2, pp. 89–195). New York: Academic Press.
Bechtel, W. (1986). The nature of scientific integration. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), Integrating scientific disciplines (pp. 3–52). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bechtel, W. (2007). Reducing psychology while maintaining its autonomy via mechanistic explanation. In M. Schouten & H. Looren de Jong (Eds.), The matter of the mind: Philosophical essays on psychology, neuroscience and reduction (pp. 172–198). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2002). Connectionism and the mind: Parallel processing, dynamics, and evolution in networks (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.
Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 173–215.
Beer, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 91–99.
Bernard, C. (1865). An introduction to the study of experimental medicine. New York: Dover.
Berzelius, J. J. (1836). Einige Ideen über bei der Bildung organischer Verbindungen in der lebenden Naturwirksame, aber bisher nicht bemerke Kraft. Jahres-Berkcht über die Fortschritte der Chemie, 15, 237–245.
Bichat, X. (1805). Recherches physiologiques sur la vie et la mort (3rd ed.). Paris: Machant.
Broca, P. (1861). Remarques sur le siége de la faculté du langage articulé, suivies d’une observation d’aphemie (perte de la parole). Bulletin de la Société Anatomique, 6, 343–357.
Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.
Cannon, W. B. (1929). Organization of physiological homeostasis. Physiological Reviews, 9, 399–431.
Clark, A. (1987). Microcognition: Philosophy, cognitive science, and parallel distributed processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Coleman, W. (1977). Biology in the nineteenth century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Origins of domain specificity: The evolution of functional organization. In L. S. Hirschfeld & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind (pp. 85–116). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cosmides, L., Tooby, J., & Barkow, J. H. (1992). Introduction: Evolutionary psychology and conceptual integration. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 3–18). New York: Oxford University Press.
Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cummins, D. D., & Allen, C. (1998). Introduction. In D. D. Cummins & C. Allen (Eds.), The evolution of mind (pp. 3–8). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cummins, R. (2000). “How does it work?” versus “What are the laws?”: Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In F. Keil & R. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 117–144). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Flourens, J. P. M. (1824). Researches expérimentales sur les propriétés et les fonctions du système nerveux dans les animaux vertébris. Paris: Crevot.
Fodor, J. A. (1980). Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 63–109.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.
Gall, F. J. (1812). Anatomie et physiologie du systême nerveaux et général, et du cerveau en particulier, avec des observations sur la possibilité de reconnoitre plusieurs dispositions intellectuelles et morales de l’homme et des animaux, par la configuration de leur têtes. Paris: F. Schoell.
Gánti, T. (1975). Organization of chemical reactions into dividing and metabolizing units: The chemotons. BioSystems, 7, 15–21.
Gánti, T. (2003). The principles of life. New York: Oxford University Press.
Garber, D. (2002). Descartes, mechanics, and the mechanical philosophy. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 26, 185–204.
Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 50–71.
Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.
Kauffman, S. (1971). Articulation of parts explanations in biology and the rational search for them. In R. C. Bluck & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), PSA, 1970 (pp. 257–272). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: D. Reidel.
Keijzer, F. (2001). Representation and behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lashley, K. S. (1929). Brain mechanisms and intelligence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lashley, K. S. (1950). In search of the engram. Symposia of the Society for Experimental Biology, IV: Physiological mechanisms in animal behaviour (pp. 454–482). New York: Academic Press.
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.
Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis: The organization of the living. In H. R. Maturana & F. J. Varela (Eds.), Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living (pp. 59–138). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: D. Reidel.
Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality: Principles and implications of cognitive psychology. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Neisser, U. (1987). Introduction: The ecological and intellectual bases of categorization. In U. Neisser (Ed.), Concepts and conceptual development: Ecological and intellectual factors in categorization (pp. 1–10). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Post, E. L. (1936). Finite combinatorial processes – formulation I. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 1, 103–105.
Richter, C. P. (1942–1943). Total self-regulatory functions in animals and human beings. Harvey Lectures, 37, 63–103.
Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: Autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34, 323–346.
Rumelhart, D. E., Smolensky, P., McClelland, J. L., & Hinton, G. E. (1986). Schemas and sequential thought processes in PDP models. In J. L. McClelland, D. E. Rumelhart, & T. P. R. Group (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 7–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Schacter, D. L., & Tulving, E. (1994). What are the memory systems of 1994? In D. L. Schacter & E. Tulving (Eds.), Memory systems, 1994 (pp. 1–38). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shettleworth, S. (2000). Modularity and the evolution of cognition. In C. Heyes & L. Huber (Eds.), The evolution of cognition (pp. 43–60). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Simon, H. A. (1996). The sciences of the artificial (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sperber, D. (1994). The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture (pp. 39–67). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sperber, D. (2001). In defense of massive modularity. In E. Dupoux (Ed.), Language, brain, and cognitive development: Essays in honor of Jacques Mehler (pp. 47–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sperber, D. (2005). Modularity and relevance: How can a massively modular mind be flexible and context-sensitive? In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Structure and content (pp. 53–68). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stein, P. S. G., & Smith, J. L. (1997). Neural and biomechanical control strategies for different forms of vertebrate hindlimb motor tasks. In P. S. G. Stein, S. Grillner, A. I. Selverston, & D. G. Stuart (Eds.), Neurons, networks, and motor behavior (pp. 61–73). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Suchman, L. (1987). Plans and situated actions: The problem of human-machine communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, L. (1993). Response to Vera and Simon's situated action: A symbolic interpretation. Cognitive Science, 17, 71–75.
Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungs problem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2nd ser., 42, 230–265.
Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 91, 345–381.
van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 615–628.
van Orden, G. C., & Paap, K. R. (1997). Functional neural images fail to discover the pieces of the mind in the parts of the brain. Philosophy of Science, 64(4), S85–S94.
van Orden, G. C., Pennington, B. F., & Stone, G. O. (2001). What do double dissociations prove? Inductive methods and isolable systems. Cognitive Science, 25, 111–172.
Virchow, R. (1858). Die cellularpathologie in ihrer begründung auf physiologische und pathologische gewebelehre. Berlin: August Hirschwald.

References

Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. London: Duckworth.
Hacking, I. (1991). A tradition of natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 91, 109–126.
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (2000). On clear and confused ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. New York: Henry Holt.
Strawson, P. F. (1974). Subject and predicate in logic and grammar. London: Methuen.