Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-29T22:06:56.254Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

2 - Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics

Paula Gottlieb
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin-Madison
John Shand
Affiliation:
Open University
Get access

Summary

The philosopher, as Aristotle is called by St Thomas Aquinas, was born in Stagira, northeast Greece, in 384 BCE, and was the most eminent of Plato's students. His father was doctor to King Amyntas of Macedon, and tradition has it that Aristotle later became the tutor of King Philip's son, the future Alexander the Great. Early on in the Nicomachean Ethics, one of his two major works on ethics, Aristotle says that his enquiry is “a sort of Politics”. Despite the lip service to kingship in his Nicomachean Ethics, the virtues Aristotle describes, especially the “nameless” ones, seem well suited to a democracy. Aristotle's interests in medicine and biology, no doubt gained from his father, lead him to compare the good human being with a doctor. The analogy had already been drawn by Protagoras, but whereas Protagoras held that whatever some person happens to think is good is good for that person, Aristotle has an objective account of happiness. What happiness is does not depend upon what anyone happens to think, although the good person will have the right view of what happiness is.

Aristotle has often been called a “eudaimonist” because he thinks that our ultimate goal in life is happiness: eudaimonia. The Greek word suggests that someone who is happy has a favourable guardian spirit (“daimōn”), and Aristotle discusses the question of how much of happiness is due to luck and how much is up to us.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×