Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-wq484 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T15:27:12.806Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Hippocratic constitutional design

from PART I - DEFINING CONSTITUTIONAL PERFORMANCE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2016

Aziz Z. Huq
Affiliation:
University of Chicago Law School
Tom Ginsburg
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Aziz Huq
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

Is there a criterion that can be used to evaluate constitutions written in Pretoria in 1996, Philadelphia in 1787, and Baghdad in 2005? Can the organic documents produced by democrats, oligarchs, tyrants, and theocracies all be judged by the same metric? This chapter, in taking up these questions, develops a benchmark for constitutional success with a general, albeit not universal, scope. That benchmark is independent of local criteria or prejudices, and relies instead on an analysis of the minimal conditions for constitutional success. Focusing my inquiry in that fashion, I contend that the most plausible touchstone of constitutional success is the avoidance of self-defeating constitutional design. It is a constitution purged of elements that conduce, perhaps unintentionally, to the breakdown or collapse of the state that the constitution endeavors to underwrite.

To situate this inquiry, it is useful to recall the dichotomy that Tom Ginsburg and I posit between metrics for evaluation of constitutional “success” that are internal and ones that are external in character. An internal criterion is one applied by a member of the polity engaged in constitutional creation or evaluation. An external criterion, by contrast, is one employed by an outsider such as a comparative constitutional scholar or a foreign advisor to constitutional drafters. So defined, the internal/external distinction turns on who applies the standard, not what the standard is. Human rights norms, for example, might be invoked both by participants to a drafting process as an internal criteria, or instead by transnational advocacy groups as a generally applicable external standard. Moreover, there is often leakage between internal and external criteria. Evaluative criteria deployed by participants in a constitution-making process are not autochthonic. They can leach their content and orientation from global intellectual currents (Ginsburg et al. 2008). Nor are external criteria necessarily loosed entirely from the gravitational force of the local circumstances of their intellectual production. Political rationality, in my view, lacks any transhistorical, acontextual form. Nevertheless, the distinction is useful insofar as it draws attention to the fact that criteria of constitutional success play different roles in different circumstances. And different standards might fit those distinct circumstances better than a single norm.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James. 2013. Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty. Reprint edition. New York: Crown Business.
Alesina, Alberto, and Spolaore, Enrico. 2005. The Size of Nations. The MIT Press.
Arjomand, Saïd Amir. 2007. “Islamic Constitutionalism.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 3 (1): 115–40. doi:10.1146/annurev.lawsocsci.3.081806.112753.Google Scholar
Bagehot, Walter. 2009. The English Constitution. Edited by Taylor, Miles. Reissue edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Blume, Lorenz, Müller, Jens, Voigt, Stefan, and Wolf, Carsten. 2008. “The Economic Effects of Constitutions: Replicating – and Extending – Persson and Tabellini.” Public Choice 139 (1–2): 197–225. doi:10.1007/s11127-008-9389-4.Google Scholar
Broome, John. 1994. “Discounting the Future.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 23 (2): 128–56.Google Scholar
Broome, John. 2000. “Cost Benefit Analysis and Population.” Journal of Legal Studies 29 (S2): 953–70. doi:10.1086/468101.Google Scholar
Castiglione, Dario. 1996. “The Political Theory of the Constitution.” Political Studies 44 (3): 417–35. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.1996.tb00592.x.Google Scholar
Cheibub, Jose Antonio. 2006. Presidentialism, Parliamentarism, and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Copland, James. 1825. The London Medical Repository.
Copp, David. 1999. “The Idea of a Legitimate State.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 28 (1): 3–45. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1999.00003.x.Google Scholar
Elkins, Zachary, Ginsburg, Tom, and Melton, James. 2009. The Endurance of National Constitutions. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Elster, Jon. 1995. “Forces and Mechanisms in the Constitution-Making Process.” Duke Law Journal 45 (2): 364–96. doi:10.2307/1372906.Google Scholar
Foweraker, J., and Landman, T.. 2002. “Constitutional Design and Democratic Performance.” Democratization 9 (2): 43–66. doi:10.1080/714000250.Google Scholar
Frey, Bruno. 1997. “A Constitution for Knaves Crowds Out Civic Virtues.” The Economic Journal 107 (443): 1043–53. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0297.1997.tb00006.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1974. “A Pareto-Consistent Libertarian Claim.” Journal of Economic Theory 7 (4): 388–410. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(74)90111-2.Google Scholar
Ginsburg, Tom. 2003. Judicial Review in New Democracies: Constitutional Courts in Asian Cases. edition used edition. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Ginsburg, Tom, Chernykh, Svitlana, and Elkins, Zachary. 2008. “Commitment and Diffusion: How and Why National Constitutions Incorporate International Law.” University of Illinois Law Review 2008: 201.Google Scholar
Ginsburg, Tom, and Huq, Aziz. 2014. “What Can Constitutions Do? The Afghan Case.” Journal of Democracy 25 (1): 116–30. doi:10.1353/jod.2014.0005.Google Scholar
Goodin, Robert E., ed. 1998. The Theory of Institutional Design. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Gray, John. 1994. “After the New Liberalism.” Social Research 61 (3): 719–35.Google Scholar
Greene, Jamal. 2009. “On the Origins of Originalism.” Texas Law Review 88: 1.Google Scholar
Gross, Oren, and Aoláin, Fionnuala Ní. 2006. Law in Times of Crisis: Emergency Powers in Theory and Practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hafner‐Burton, Emilie M., and Tsutsui, Kiyoteru. 2005. “Human Rights in a Globalizing World: The Paradox of Empty Promises.” American Journal of Sociology 110 (5): 1373–411. doi:10.1086/428442.Google Scholar
Hafner‐Burton, Emilie M., and Tsutsui, Kiyoteru. 2007. “Justice Lost! The Failure of International Human Rights Law to Matter Where Needed Most.” Journal of Peace Research 44 (4): 407–25. doi:10.1177/0022343307078942.Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 2015. “Why a Constitution?” In Social and Political Foundations of Constitutions. Edited by Versteeg, Mila, and Gilligan, Dennis. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Harsanyi, John C. 1975. “Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality? A Critique of John Rawls's Theory.” American Political Science Review 69 (02): 594–606. doi:10.2307/1959090.Google Scholar
Hirschl, Ran. 2007. Towards Juristocracy: The Origins and Consequences of the New Constitutionalism. Cambridge, MA; London: Harvard University Press.
Hulsebosch, Daniel J. 1998. “The Constitution in the Glass Case and Constitutions in Action.” Law and History Review 16 (02): 397–401. doi:10.2307/744108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huq, Aziz Z. 2013a. “The Function of Article V.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 162: 1165.Google Scholar
Huq, Aziz Z. 2013b. “Libertarian Separation of Powers.” New York University Journal of Law and Liberty 8: 1006.Google Scholar
King, Gary and Zeng, Langche. 2001. “Improving Forecasts of State Failure.” World Politics 53 (04): 623–58. doi:10.1353/wp.2001.0018.Google Scholar
Kohlscheen, Emanuel. 2010. “Sovereign Risk: Constitutions Rule.” Oxford Economic Papers 62 (1): 62–85. doi:10.1093/oep/gpp005.Google Scholar
Kysar, Douglas A. 2007. “Discounting … on Stilts.” University of Chicago Law Review 74: 119.Google Scholar
Linz, Juan J. 1990. “The Perils of Presidentialism.” Journal of Democracy 1 (1): 51–69.Google Scholar
Lipsey, R. G., and Lancaster, Kelvin. 1956. “The General Theory of Second Best.” The Review of Economic Studies 24 (1): 11–32. doi:10.2307/2296233.Google Scholar
Maddox, G., 1989. “Constitution.” In Political Innovation and Conceptual Change. Edited by Ball, Terence, Farr, James, and Hanson, Russell L., 50–65. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Maier, Charles S. 2014. Leviathan 2.0: Inventing Modern Statehood. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Maier, Pauline. 2011. Ratification: The People Debate the Constitution, 1787–1788. 5.8.2011 edition. Simon & Schuster.
March, James G., and Olsen, Johan P.. 1975. “The Uncertainty of the Past: Organizational Learning under Ambiguity.” European Journal of Political Research 3 (2): 147–71. doi:10.1111/j.1475-6765.1975.tb00521.x.Google Scholar
McGinnis, John O., and Rappaport, Michael B.. 2013. Originalism and the Good Constitution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Miller, Gary. 2000. “Rational Choice and Dysfunctional Institutions.” Governance 13 (4): 535–47. doi:10.1111/0952-1895.00145.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C., and Weingast, Barry R.. 1989. “Constitutions and Commitment: The Evolution of Institutions Governing Public Choice in Seventeenth-Century England.” The Journal of Economic History 49 (04): 803–32. doi:10.1017/S0022050700009451.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 2007. “Constitutions and Capabilities: Perception against Lofty Formalism.” Harvard Law Review 121: 4.Google Scholar
Oakeshott, Michael. 1991. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. Expanded edition. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Offe, Claus. 1996. “Designing Institutions in Eastern European Transitions.” In The Theory of Institutional Design. Edited by Goodin, Robert E.. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Olsen, Johan P. 1997. “Institutional Design in Democratic Contexts.” Journal of Political Philosophy 5 (3): 203–29. doi:10.1111/1467-9760.00032.Google Scholar
Perrow, Charles. 2011. The Next Catastrophe: Reducing Our Vulnerabilities to Natural, Industrial, and Terrorist Disasters. With a new preface by the author edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Persson, Torsten, and Tabellini, Guido. 2005. The Economic Effects of Constitutions. The MIT Press.
Peterson, Martin. 2009. An Introduction to Decision Theory. edition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Pierson, Paul. 2000. “The Limits of Design: Explaining Institutional Origins and Change.” Governance 13 (4): 475–99. doi:10.1111/0952-1895.00142.Google Scholar
Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1987. “The Idea of a Constitution.” Journal of Legal Education 37 (2): 167–69.Google Scholar
Preuss, Ulrich K. 1991. “The Politics of Constitution Making: Transforming Politics into Constitutions.” Law & Policy 13 (2): 107–23. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9930.1991.tb00061.x.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam, and Limongi, Fernando. 1993. “Political Regimes and Economic Growth.” The Journal of Economic Perspectives 7 (3): 51–69.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1972. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Rawls, John 1974. “Some Reasons for the Maximin Criterion.” The American Economic Review 64 (2): 141–46.Google Scholar
Rosenn, Keith S. 1990. “Brazil's New Constitution: An Exercise in Transient Constitutionalism for a Transitional Society.” The American Journal of Comparative Law 38 (4): 773–802. doi:10.2307/840612.Google Scholar
Rotberg, Robert I. 2002. “The New Nature of Nation‐State Failure.” The Washington Quarterly 25 (3): 83–96. doi:10.1162/01636600260046253.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997. Rousseau: “The Social Contract” and Other Later Political Writings. Edited by Gourevitch, Victor. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2012. The Major Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Two “Discourses” and the “Social Contract.” Edited by Scott, John T.. Reprint edition. University of Chicago Press.
Samida, Dexter, and Weisbach, David A.. 2007. “Paretian Intergenerational Discounting.” University of Chicago Law Review 74: 145.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1970. “The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal.” Journal of Political Economy 78 (1): 152–57.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1979a. “Personal Utilities and Public Judgements: Or What's Wrong with Welfare Economics.” The Economic Journal 89 (355): 537–58. doi:10.2307/2231867.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1979b. “Utilitarianism and Welfarism.” The Journal of Philosophy 76 (9): 463–89. doi:10.2307/2025934.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya, and Williams, Bernard, eds. 1982. Utilitarianism and Beyond. printing edition. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Stanger, Allison. 2004. “How Important Are New Constitutions for Democratic Consolidation? Lessons from the Post-Communist States.” Democratization 11 (3), 1–26. doi:10.1080/1351034042000238149.Google Scholar
Stourzh, G. 1998. “Constitution: Changing Meanings of the Term from the Early Seventeenth to the Late Eighteenth Century.” In Conceptual Change and the Constitution. Edited by Ball, Terence and Pocock, J. G. A., 35–54. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
Sunstein, Cass R. 1991. “Constitutionalism and Secession.” The University of Chicago Law Review 58 (2): 633–70. doi:10.2307/1599969.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 1995. “Incompletely Theorized Agreements.” Harvard Law Review 108 (7): 1733–72. doi:10.2307/1341816.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 2009. Worst-Case Scenarios. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Vermeule, Adrian. 2013. The Constitution of Risk. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Waldstreicher, David. 2010. Slavery's Constitution: From Revolution to Ratification. edition. New York; Godalming: Hill and Wang.
Weinstock, Daniel. 2001. “Constitutionalizing the Right to Secede.” Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (2): 182–203. doi:10.1111/1467-9760.00124.Google Scholar
Weisbach, David, and Sunstein, Cass R.. 2009. “Climate Change and Discounting the Future: A Guide for the Perplexed.” Yale Law & Policy Review 27 (2): 433–57.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1973. “A Critique of Utilitarianism.” In Utilitarianism: For and Against. Edited by Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard, 77–150. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×