Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-05T22:16:53.521Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

17 - Problems of knowledge and action: Fate, fortune, providence and human freedom

from PART 2 - PHILOSOPHY AND ITS PARTS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

These concepts constitute one of the fundamental philosophical problems about human destiny in general and about human actions in particular. Is the individual a rigidly defined link in a universal chain of being in which birth, life and death have been entirely preordained by physical cosmic forces? Or can the individual control his life and, by means of more or less independent decisions, direct it to some consciously chosen goal? Such questions are as old as humanity itself. Sometimes they are coloured by religious beliefs or magical and astrological superstitions and scarcely emerge into popular awareness. At other times they stimulate the philosophical reflections which are humanity's first steps away from a dark and fearful fate towards a rational understanding of natural and historical events.

THE PROBLEM IN ANTIQUITY AND THE MIDDLE AGES

In antiquity philosophy could not entirely disburden itself of ειμαρμενη the mysterious fate which ruled men and gods, impervious to protests and invocations. Except for thinkers like Plato, Aristotle and Plotinus, who achieved a profound and rigorous grasp of the first principle, the bulk of Greek, Hellenistic and Roman thought tended to be drawn by its monistic and materialist metaphysics into a kind of cosmic necessity which denied human freedom and excluded providence (πρóνοια) and the contingency of events (τυχη). The first centuries of the Christian era teemed with tracts about fate. One current was represented by Alexander of Aphrodisias, who, following Aristotle, asserted the possibility of contingency, that is, ενδεχóμενον By contrast, evolving Neoplatonism petrified the causal links between the degrees of being, thus unleashing a frenzy of magical-mystical practices which profoundly affected the purity of man's religious relationship with the divine.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boisset, J. (1962). Érasme et Luther: Libre ou serf arbitre?, Paris.Google Scholar
Cassirer, E. (1927). Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophie der Renaissance, Berlin–Leipzig.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corsano, A. (1961b). ‘Il Liber de ludo aleae di Girolamo Cardano: ragione e fortuna’, Giornale critico della filosofia italiana, 40.Google Scholar
De Nichilo, M. (1975). I poemi astrologici di Giovanni Pontano, Bari.Google Scholar
Di Napoli, G. (1970). ‘Libertà e fato in Pietro Pomponazzi’, in Studi in onore di Antonio Corsano, Manduria.Google Scholar
Di Napoli, G. (1971). Lorenzo Valla: filosofia e religione nell'umanesimo italiano, Rome.Google Scholar
Doren, A. (1922–3). ‘Fortuna im Mittelalter und in der Renaissance’, Vorträge der Bibliothek Warburg, 2, 1.Google Scholar
Erasmus, Desiderius (1703–6). Opera omnia, ed. Leclerc, J., 10 vols., Leiden (repr. Hildesheim 1961–2).Google Scholar
Erasmus, Desiderius (1970). La Philosophie chrétienne, ed. Mesnard, P., Paris.Google Scholar
Federici Vescovini, G. (1979). Astrologia e scienza: La crisi dell'aristotelismo sul cadere del Trecento e Biagio Pelacani da Parma, Florence.Google Scholar
Federici Vescovini, G. (1983). ‘Arti’ e filosofia nel secolo XIV, Florence.Google Scholar
Garin, E. (1958a). Studi sul platonismo medievale, Florence.Google Scholar
Garin, E. (1966). Storia della filosofia italiana, new edn, 3 vols., Turin.Google Scholar
Gasperetti, L. (1941). ‘II De fato, fortuna et casu di Coluccio Salutati’, Rinascita, 4.Google Scholar
Gilmore, M. P. (1952). Jean Duns Scot: Introduction à ses positions fondamentales, Paris.Google Scholar
Gottschalk, (1945). Oeuvres ⃛héologiques et grammaticales, ed. Lambot, C., Louvain.Google Scholar
Graiff, F. (1976). ‘I prodigi e l'astrologia nei comment di Pietro Pomponazzi al De caelo, alla Meteora e al De generatione’, Medioevo, 2.Google Scholar
Heitmann, K. (1958). Fortuna und Virtus: Eine Studie zu Petrarcas Lebensweisheit, Cologne–Graz.Google Scholar
Luther, Martin (1883–). Werke, Weimar.Google Scholar
Maier, A. (1966). Die Vorläufer Galileis im 14. Jahrhundert, 2nd edn, Rome.Google Scholar
Masai, F. (1956). Pléthon et le platonisme de Mistra, Paris.Google Scholar
Mauro, L. (1981). ‘Il problema del fato in Boezio e Tommaso d' Aquino’, in Atti del congresso internazionale di studi boeziani, Rome.Google Scholar
Piccolomini, Alessandro (1551). Della filosofia naturale, Rome.Google Scholar
Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni (1942). De hominis dignitate, Heptaplus, De ente et uno, e scritti vari, ed. Garin, E., Florence.Google Scholar
Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni (1946–52). Disputationes adversus astrologiam divinatricem, ed. Garin, E., 2 vols., Florence.Google Scholar
Pine, M. (1973). ‘Pietro Pomponazzi and the scholastic doctrine of free will’, Rivista critica di storia della filosofia, 28.Google Scholar
Pletho, Georgius Gemistus (1858). Traité des lois, ed. Alexandre, C., trans. Pellissier, A., Paris (repr. Amsterdam, 1966).Google Scholar
Poggio, Bracciolini (1964–9). Opera omnia, ed. Fubini, R., 4 vols., Turin.Google Scholar
Pomponazzi, Pietro (1556). De naturalium effectuum admirandorum causis seu de incantationibus, Basle.Google Scholar
Pomponazzi, Pietro (1957). Libri quinque de fato, de libero arbitrio et de praedestinatione, ed. Lemay, R., Lugano.Google Scholar
Pontano, Giovanni (1518). Opera, Venice.Google Scholar
Porzio, Simone (1553). De rerum naturalium principiis libri II, Naples.Google Scholar
Rahner, K. (1975). ‘Grazia e libertà’, in Enciclopedia teologica ‘Sacramentum mundi’, IV, Brescia, PP.Google Scholar
Saitta, G. (1961). Il pensiero italiano nell'umanesimo e nel Rinasċimento, 2nd edn, 3 vols., Florence.Google Scholar
Salutati, Coluccio (1891–1911). Epistolario, ed. Novati, F., 4 vols., Rome.Google Scholar
Salutati, Coluccio (1985). De fato et for tuna, ed. Bianca, C., Florence.Google Scholar
Sasso, G. (1953). ‘Qualche osservazione sul problema della virtù e della fortuna nell'Alberti’, Il mulino, 2.Google Scholar
Tateo, F. (1960a). Astrologia e moralità in Giovanni Pontano, Bari.Google Scholar
Taylor, J. W. (1925a). Theodore Gaza's De Fato, Toronto.Google Scholar
Testi umanistici sulla retorica (1953). ed. Garin, E. et al, Rome.Google Scholar
Thorndike, L. (1923–58). A History of Magic and Experimental Science, 8 vols., New York.Google Scholar
Valla, Lorenzo (1934). De libero arbitrio, ed. Anfossi, M., Florence.Google Scholar
Walker, D. P. (1958). Spiritual and Demonic Magic from Ficino to Campanella, London.Google Scholar
Zambelli, P. (1973b). ‘Il problema della magia naturale nel Rinascimento’, Rivista critica di storia della filosofia, 28.Google Scholar
Zambelli, P. (1975). ‘I problemi metodologici del necromante Agostino Nifo’, Medioevo, 1.Google Scholar
Zambruno, E. (1983). Teodoro di Beza di fronte a un ‘sicofante’Milan.Google Scholar
Zanier, G. (1977). La medicina astrologica e la sua teoria: Marsilio Ficino e i suoi critici contemporanei, Rome.Google Scholar
Zanier, G. (1981). ‘Struttura e significato delle Disputationes pichiane’, Giornale critico della filosofia italiana, 40.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×