Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T14:15:54.417Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Parochialism, Cosmopolitanism, and Justice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2011

M. N. S. Sellers
Affiliation:
University of Baltimore
Get access

Summary

Any careful consideration of the international legal order will reach the same conclusion as every author in this volume, which is that parochialism and cosmopolitanism stand together at the center of the theoretical and historical foundations of international law. The first problem in global justice is where to draw the boundary between the two. The modern law of nations as developed by Grotius, Vattel, and Wheaton began with “those rules of conduct which reason deduces, as consonant to justice and common good, from the nature of the society existing among independent nations.” This doctrine assumes both a cosmopolitan standard (“reason”) and parochial communities (“nations”). The difficulty lies in distinguishing the proper borders between the jurisdiction of international law, national law, individual autonomy, and other parochial communities of specialized legal order. Justice and the common good determine what is cosmopolitan, what should be parochial, and where to draw the legal boundaries of blood, soil, power, and authority.

Hugo Grotius stated the problem very well when he refuted Carneades’ primitive realism at the beginning of his discussion of the laws of war and peace. Law arises from the desire to maintain social harmony, and each person and every social group has its own role to play in doing so. We owe a duty of care and obedience to our fellow citizens, but also to our fellow human beings. The trick is to avoid confusing the law of nations with what is the law only of certain peoples and vice versa. Grotius understood that international law governs matters of international concern. Other questions belong to states, or to the people themselves. Tradition excluded rules governing (for example) the acquisition of property from international law, or the seizure of goods for debt, or the decision of nations whether to trade (or not) with others.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Wheaton, HenryElements of International LawBoston 1866Google Scholar
Madison, quoting JamesAn Examination of the British Doctrine which subjects to capture a Neutral Trade not open in a Time of PeaceLondon 1806 41Google Scholar
Sellers, M. N. S.Republican Principles in International LawBasingstoke 2006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellers, MortimerAn Introduction to the Value of Autonomy in Law,Autonomy in the LawDordrecht 2008 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Vattel, EmerLe Droit des Gens ou principes de la loi naturelle appliqués à la conduite et aux affaires des Nations et des SouverainsLondon 1758Google Scholar
Jouannet, EmmanuelleEmer de Vattel et l’émergence doctrinale du droit international classiqueParis 1998Google Scholar
Sellers, M. N. S.The Republican Foundations of International LawLegal RepublicanismOxford 2009 187Google Scholar
1948
Bederman, David J.International Law in AntiquityOxford 2001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langdon, Stephen H.Gardiner, Alan H.The Treaty of Alliance between Hattusili, King of the Hittites and the Pharaoh Ramesses II of Egypt 6 Journal of Egyptian Archaeology179 1920Google Scholar
1949
Oppenheim, LassaInternational Law: A TreatiseLondon 1905 3Google Scholar
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948
Oppenheim, LassaInternational Law: A TreatiseLondon 1905 3Google Scholar
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969
Sellers, M. N. S.Regents Lecture: The Value and Purpose of Law 33 University of Baltimore Law Review146 2004Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen 2004
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights 1966
Ibid 1966
1868
Sellers, M. N. S.Universal Human Rights in the Law of the United States,American Journal of Comparative Law 533 2010Google Scholar
Robertson, A. H.The European Court of Human Rights, 9 American Journal of Comparative Law1 1960CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Statute of the Inter-American Court on Human Rights 1980
Lorca, Arnulf BeckerUniversal International Law: Nineteenth-Century Histories of Imposition and Appropriation, 51 Harvard Journal of International Law 2010Google Scholar
Simpson, GerryGreat Powers and Outlaw States: Unequal Sovereigns in the International Legal OrderCambridge 2004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, IanBrilmayer, LeaGlobal JusticeNew York 1999Google Scholar
Charter of the United Nations 1945
1946
Charter of the United Nations 1945
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948
1833
Shapiro, IanBrilmayer, LeaGlobal JusticeNew York 1999Google Scholar
Wickard v. Filburn 1942
Charter of the United Nations 1945
Davies, D. J. L.Domestic Jurisdiction: A Limitation on International Law,Transactions of the Grotius Society 60 1946 65Google Scholar
United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change 1992
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court 2002
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women 1981
Convention Against Transnational Organized Crime 2003
Convention on Biological Diversity 1993
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights 1976
United Nations Convention to Combat Desertification 1996
United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods 1988
Doha Declaration 2005
Anghie, AntonyImperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International LawCambridge 2004Google Scholar
Charter of the United Nations 1945
Doha Declaration 2005
Simpson, GerryGreat Powers and Outlaw States: Unequal Sovereigns in the International Legal OrderCambridge 2004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markus, JosephGrandes puissances, petites nations et le problème de l'organisation internationalNeuchatel 1946Google Scholar
1945
Doha Declaration 2005
Human Rights in China 1991
Mill, John StuartOn Liberty 1859 On Liberty and Other WritingsCambridge13Google Scholar
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948
1858
Roth, Brad R.Governmental Illegitimacy in International LawOxford 1999Google Scholar
American Service-Members’ Protection Act 2002
Ignatieff, MichaelAmerican Exceptionalism and Human RightsPrinceton 2005Google Scholar
2005
Medellín v. Texas 2008
552 2008
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948
1966
1966
1966
1966
1948 2

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×