Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-rkxrd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T07:38:22.425Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - Creation, aesthetics, market: origins of the modern concept of art

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2011

Annie Becq
Affiliation:
University of Caen
Get access

Summary

The concept of art is a historical one. When Saint Thomas uses the word “art” he means something completely different than a modern thinker, as Etienne Gilson made a point of observing in 1958. Gilson was expressing his agreement with the then most recent essay on Thomist aesthetics, that of Umberto Eco, according to whom, “As a matter of fact, the scholastic philosophers never occupied themselves ex professo with art or its aesthetic value.” And long ago P. O. Kristeller meticulously followed the misadventures of the Greek and Latin equivalents of this term in the West since antiquity, up to the constitution of what he called “the modern system of the fine arts.” This was clearly achieved in France around the mid–eighteenth century with the celebrated treatise of the abbé Batteux, Les beaux-arts reduits à un même principe, published in 1746 and destined for considerable success both in France and abroad.

Underlying the constellation of arts Batteux called “fine” (poetry, painting, sculpture, music, dance), to the exclusion of other arts called “liberal” or “mechanical,” was a concept naming their common essence, the imitation of beautiful nature, la belle nature. This is not the concept that modern consciousness associates with that of art. The fundamental notions of modern aesthetics crystallize around the idea of creation: in the work of art, understood as an organic totality, are expressed the autonomy of the beautiful and the irreducible originality of the genius whose unique gesture has engendered it. Consequently, this concept of the work, fruit of human activity, has taken the place of the idea of beauty (which designates qualities possibly independent of human activity) as a focus for reflection on the arts.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×