Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-01T13:53:49.454Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Gary Gutting
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
What Philosophers Know
Case Studies in Recent Analytic Philosophy
, pp. 243 - 247
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Audi, Robert, The Good and the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.
Bealer, George, “Intuitions and the Autonomy of Philosophy,” in DePaul, and Ramsey, (eds.), 201–39.
Burge, Tyler, “Logic and Analyticity,” Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 (2003), 199–249.Google Scholar
Burgess, John, “Quine, Analyticity and Philosophy of Mathematics,” Philosophical Quarterly 54 (2004), 38–55.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David, The Conscious Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Chalmers, David,“Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument,” in Ludlow, P., Nagasawa, Y., and Stoljar, D. (eds.), There's Something about Mary, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004, 269–98.
Chalmers, David, “The Two-Dimensional Argument Against Materialism,” in his The Character of Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming (a draft is available on Chalmers' website at http://consc.net/papers/2dargument.html)
Chomsky, Noam, Review of Verbal Behavior, Language 35 (1959), 26–58.CrossRef
Clark, Michael, “Knowledge and Grounds: A Comment on Mr. Gettier's Paper,” Analysis 24(2) (1963), 46–8.Google Scholar
Creath, Richard (ed.), Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine–Carnap Correspondence and Related Work, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990.
Cummins, Robert, “Reflections on Reflective Equilibrium,” in DePaul, and Ramsey, (eds), 113–27.
Daniels, Norman, “Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,” Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), 256–82.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donals, “Quine's Externalism,”Grazer Philosophische Studien, 66 (2003), 281–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Zombic Hunch: Extinction of an Intuition?,” in O'Hear, A. (ed.), Philosophy at the New Millennium, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, 27–43.
DePaul, Michael R., “Reflective Equilibrium and Foundationalism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1986), 59–69.Google Scholar
DePaul, Michael R.,“Why Bother with Reflective Equilibrium?,” in DePaul, and Ramsey, (eds.), 293–309.
DePaul, M. R. and Ramsey, W. (eds.), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998.
DeRose, Keith, “Plantinga, Presumption, Possibility and the Problem of Evil,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1990), 497–512.Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth, “The Causal Theory of Names,” Collected Papers, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Fitch, G. W., Saul Kripke, Montreal: McGill Queen's University Press, 2004.
Flew, Anthony and MacIntyre, Alasdair (eds.), New Essays in Philosophical Theology, London: Macmillan, 1955.
Fodor, Jerry, “Water's Water Everywhere,” London Review of Books, October 21, 2004.
Frankfurt, Harry, “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility,” Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969), 829–39.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael, “Kuhn and Logical Empiricism,” in Nickles, Thomas (ed.), Thomas Kuhn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, 19–44.
Gettier, Edmund, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?,” Analysis 23 (1963), 121–3.Google Scholar
Gibson, Roger F. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Quine, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Giere, Ronald, “Kuhn's Legacy for North American Philosophy of Science,” Social Studies of Science 27 (1997), 496–8.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J., Glürt, K., and Keil, G. (eds.), Fifty Years of Quine's “Two Dogmas” (Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 [2003]), 1. Also published as a book by Rodopi, 2003.
Goldman, Alvin, “A Causal Theory of Knowing,” Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), 335–72.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin,“What is Justified Belief?,” in Pappas, George (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, 1–23.
Grice, H. P. and Strawson, P. F., “In Defense of a Dogma,” Philosophical Review 55 (1956), 141–58.Google Scholar
Gutting, Gary, Pragmatic Liberalism and the Critique of Modernity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Hardcastle, Valerie Gray, “The Why of Consciousness: A Non-Issue for Materialists,” in Shear, Jonathan (ed.), Explaining Consciousness – The “Hard Problem,”Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997, 61–8.
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul and Sankey, Howard (eds.), Incommensurability and Related Matters, Boston: Kluwer, 2001.
Hughes, Christopher, Kripke: Names, Necessity, and Identity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Jackson, Frank, From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Jackson, Frank,“Reference and Description Revisited,” in Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 12: Language, Mind, and Ontology, Oxford: Blackwell, 1998, 201–18.
Katz, Jerrold, “Names without Bearers,” The Philosophical Review 103 (1994), 1–39.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon, “The Mind–Body Problem at Century's Turn,” in Leiter, Brian (ed.), The Future for Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004, 129–52.
Kirk, Robert, “Zombies v. Materialists,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Vol. 48 (1974), 135–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip, “Theories, Theorists and Theoretical Change,” The Philosophical Review 87 (1978), 519–47.Google Scholar
Klein, Peter, “A Proposed Definition of Propositional Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), 471–82.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980.
Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, second edition, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970 [first published 1962].
Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970.
Laudan, Laurens, Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.
Lewis, David, “Are We Free to Break the Laws?,” in his Philosophical Papers, Volume II, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986, 291–8.
Lewis, David,“Elusive Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1996), 549–67.Google Scholar
Loar, Brian, “Phenomenal States (Revised),” in Ludlow, P., Nagasawa, Y., and Stoljar, D. (eds.), There's Something about Mary, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004, 219–39.
Lycan, William, “Definition in a Quinean World,” in Fetzer, J., Shatz, D., and Schlesinger, G. (eds.), Definitions and Definability: Philosophical Perspectives, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991, 111–31.
Lycan, William,“On the Gettier Problem Problem,” Hetherington, in Stephen (ed.), Epistemology Futures, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, 148–68.
Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., and Stich, S., “Semantics Cross-Cultural Style,” Cognition 92 (2004), B1–B12.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L., The Miracle of Theism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982.
Martin, Michael, Atheism: A Philosophical Justification, Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990.
McDowell, John, “Towards Rehabilitating Objectivity,” in Brandom, Robert B. (ed.), Rorty and His Critics, Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 109–23.
McGinn, Colin, “Can We Solve the Mind–Body Problem?,” Mind, New Series, 98 (1989), 349–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Conceiving the Impossible and the Mind–Body Problem,” Philosophy 73 (1998), 337–52.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?,” The Philosophical Review 83 (1974), 435–50.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew, Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1984.
Plantinga, Alvin, God and Other Minds, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1967.
Plantinga, Alvin, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974.
Plantinga, Alvin, Warranted Christian Belief, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Putnam, Hilary, “The Analytic and the Synthetic,” in his Mind, Language, and Reality, Philosophical Papers, Volume II, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975. [First published 1962.]
Putnam, Hilary, “The Greatest Logical Positivist,” in his Realism with a Human Face, ed. Conant, James, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.
Putnam, Hilary, Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Quine, W. V. O., “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in his From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953.
Quine, W. V., “Two Dogmas in Retrospect,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1991), 265–74.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1960.
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Richard, Rorty, “Response to John McDowell,” in Brandom, R. (ed.), Rorty and His Critics, Oxford: Blackwell, 2000, 123–8.
Rorty, Richard, “An Imaginative Philosopher: The Legacy of W. V. Quine” [obituary notice], Chronicle of Higher Education, February 2, 2001.
Rorty, Richard, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Rorty, Richard, Philosophy as Cultural Politics (Philosophical Papers, Volume IV), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979.
Salmon, Nathan, Reference and Essence, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982, 23–31.
Israel, Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1967.
Samuel, Scheffler, “Rawls and Utilitarianism,” in Freeman, Samuel (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
Searle, John, Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Shapere, Dudley, “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,” The Philosophical Review 73 (1964), 383–94.Google Scholar
Shope, Robert K., The Analysis of Knowledge, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1983.
Shope, Robert K., “Conditions and Analyses of Knowing,” in Moser, Paul (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, 25–70
Singer, Peter, “Philosophers Are Back on the Job,” The New York Times Magazine, July 7, 1974, 6–7; 17–20.Google Scholar
Soames, Scott, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume I: The Dawn of Analysis, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003.
Soames, ScottPhilosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume II: The Age of Meaning, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003.
Sosa, E. and Kim, J. (eds.), Epistemology: An Anthology, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2000, 340–53.
Stoljar, Daniel, “Physicalism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (online), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physicalism/
Swoyer, Chris, “How Ontology Might Be Possible: Explanation and Inference in Metaphysics,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXIII (1999), 100–31.Google Scholar
Inwagen, Peter, An Essay on Free Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983.
Inwagen, Peter, “Freedom to Break the Laws,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXVIII (2004), 334–50Google Scholar
Inwagen, Peter, “Free Will Remains a Mystery,” in Kane, Robert (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, 158–77.
Inwagen, Peter, “The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism,” Philosophical Studies 27 (1975), 185–99.Google Scholar
Weatherson, Brian, “What Good Are Counterexamples?,” Philosophical Studies 115 (2003), 1–31.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., and Stich, S., “Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions,” Philosophical Topics 29 (2001), 429–60.Google Scholar
Whitehead, Alfred North, Adventures of Ideas, New York: Free Press, 1967 [first published 1933].
Williams, Bernard, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985.
Williamson, Timothy, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell, 2007.
Zammito, John H., A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post-Positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004.
Zimmerman, Dean, “Materialism and Survival,” in Stump, E. and Murray, M. (eds.), Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions, Oxford: Blackwell, 1999, 379–86.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Gary Gutting, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: What Philosophers Know
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841156.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Gary Gutting, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: What Philosophers Know
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841156.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Gary Gutting, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: What Philosophers Know
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841156.012
Available formats
×