Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-11T18:05:05.338Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - From the units of inheritance to the origin of species

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Lucio Vinicius
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Get access

Summary

By the time of Darwin and Wallace's death the belief in evolution and descent with modification of species was well established, but enthusiasm for natural selection as the mechanism or law of evolution remained meagre until the 1930s (Bennettt, 1999). The most likely reason for scepticism was that the genetic theories considered by Darwin and other naturalists, including pangenesis (the origin of the hereditary material from the fusion of body organ samples or ‘gemules’; Darwin, 1868), Nägeli's blending theory (the averaging of parents' traits in sexually produced offspring; see Ospovat, 1980 and Berry, 2000) and inheritance of acquired characters (see Mayr and Provine, 1980) failed to account adequately for inheritable variation in natural populations and were at odds with experimental work done by geneticists (Osborn, 1926). Crampton (1928) believed that ‘little if any understanding of the origin of organic types can be gained through the study of genera, species or even varieties, after they have arisen … the geneticists and they alone are working on the fundamental dynamics of organic differentiation’. For this reason, natural selection was still struggling to gain respect among biologists 70 years after its birth: as summed up by Watson (1929), ‘the only two “theories of evolution” which have gained any general currency, those of Lamarck and of Darwin, rest on a most insecure basis’.

Less than a decade after Watson's remarks were published, natural selection had become the one and only theory of evolution for most biologists.

Type
Chapter
Information
Modular Evolution
How Natural Selection Produces Biological Complexity
, pp. 38 - 71
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×