Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T11:23:33.992Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Molecular “cytogenetics”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 August 2009

Raphael Falk
Affiliation:
Hebrew University of Jerusalem
Get access

Summary

Starting with the achievements of microscopists in the 1880s, attention was directed at the cell's nucleus and its chromosomes as the carriers of the genetic material, to the exclusion of the role of the cytoplasm and all its components (the cell membrane was considered inherently irrelevant). Nuclei were composed of nucleo-proteins. Based on the repetitive tetranucleotide structure hypothesis, first proposed by Hermann Steudel in 1906 and developed by Phoebus Levene in 1931 (Deichmann, 2004), the prevailing conception was that nucleic acids comprised stoichiometric aggregates of nucleotide tetrads. Proteins, being the material of enzymes, were celebrated at the first half of the twentieth century as the essence of life. They seemed to be able to provide the diversity that would be expected of the material of heredity thanks to the large number of known amino acids involved in their composition. Toward the end of the 1940s Fred Singer directly demonstrated the diversity of polypeptide chains, and Wendell Stanley's initial erroneous claim in 1935 that crystallized tobacco mosaic virus was a pure self-replicating protein (a study for which Stanley was awarded the 1946 Nobel Prize) further upheld the centrality of proteins in the deliberations on the nature of the hereditary material (see Deichmann, 2004; Lederberg, 1994). These studies were foreign to genetic analysis and its methodology (see Chapter 1).

Two kinds of nucleic acids were conceived, named after their main source at the time, alkali-stable “thymus” nucleic acid, and alkali-labile “yeast” nucleic acid; corresponding to today's DNA and RNA, respectively.

Type
Chapter
Information
Genetic Analysis
A History of Genetic Thinking
, pp. 191 - 201
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×