Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T13:07:39.867Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

18 - Non-therapeutic pediatric interventions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 October 2009

David Benatar
Affiliation:
Associate Professor University of Cape Town, South Africa
Peter A. Singer
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
A. M. Viens
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

A five-year-old boy who has acute lymphoblastic leukemia was originally treated with combination chemotherapy and achieved remission. Within several months his disease relapsed. His doctors have determined that allogenic bone marrow transplantation offers the greatest chance of a sustained remission. His one-year-old sister is the best match. Their mother has agreed to the sister being a donor, but their father has reservations about putting her through the procedure and suggests that his wife, although not quite as good a match, should be the donor.

What are non-therapeutic pediatric interventions?

Non-therapeutic pediatric interventions, such as harvesting a child's bone marrow, are medical interventions that are not intended to benefit medically the child upon whom they are performed. Therefore, where such interventions are proposed or undertaken, they have some other purpose. In the case opening this chapter, the purpose of harvesting J's bone marrow is to save the life of I.

The word “therapeutic” can be understood in broader and narrower ways. In the narrower sense, it excludes prophylactic interventions – namely those that are not intended to cure some condition the child currently has but to prevent an adverse medical condition later. Because prophylactic interventions are morally similar (even if not identical) to narrowly therapeutic ones, I shall group these together and thus use “therapeutic” in the broader sense that includes prophylactic measures. Non-therapeutic interventions are then those that neither cure nor prevent disease or impairment in those on whom they are performed.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Benatar, D. (ed.) (2006). Cutting to the Core: Exploring the Ethics of Contested Surgeries. Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Benatar, M. and Benatar, D. (2003). Between prophylaxis and child abuse: the ethics of neonatal circumcision. Am J Bioethics 3: 35–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, C. (1978). Children, medical research and informed consent. J Soc Philos 9: 14–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawson, A. (2005). The determination of “best interests” in relation to childhood vaccinations. Bioethics 19: 188–205.Google ScholarPubMed
Fleck, L. M. (2004). Children and organ donation: some cautionary remarks. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 13: 161–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jansen, L. A. (2004). Child organ donation, family autonomy, and intimate attachments. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 13: 133–42.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ladd, R. E. (2004). The child as living donor: parental consent and child assent. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 13: 143–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redmon, R. B. (1986). How children can be respected as “ends” yet still be used as subjects in non-therapeutic research. J Med Ethics 12: 77–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sommerville, M. (2000). Altering baby boys' bodies: the ethics of infant male circumcision. In The Ethical Canary: Science, Society, and the Human Spirit. Toronto: Viking, pp. 202–19.Google Scholar
Viens, A. M. (2004). Value judgment, harm and religious liberty. J Med Ethics 30: 241–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zinner, S. (2004). Cognitive development and pediatric consent to organ donation. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 13: 125–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×