Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T06:10:57.147Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 August 2009

Graham Oppy
Affiliation:
Monash University, Victoria
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Arguing about Gods , pp. 427 - 444
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, R. 1971. “The Logical Structure of Anselm's Argument.” Philosophical Review 80: 28–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, R. 1995. “Introductory Note to *1970.” In K. Gödel, Collected Works, vol. 3: Unpublished Essays and Lectures, Feferman, Solomon (ed.). New York: Oxford University Press, 388–402.Google Scholar
Almeida, M., and Oppy, G.. 2003. “Sceptical Theism and the Evidential Argument from Evil.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81, no. 4: 496–516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. 1983. “Christian Experience and Christian Belief.” In Plantinga, A. and Wolterstorff, N. (eds.), Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Alston, W. 1991/6. “The Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cognitive Condition.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 97–125.
Alston, W. 1996. “Some (Temporarily) Final Thoughts on Evidential Arguments from Evil.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 311–32.
Anderson, C. 1990. “Some Emendations on Gödel's Ontological Proof.” Faith and Philosophy 7: 291–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, R. 1995. “Recent Criticisms and Defences of Pascal's Wager.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 37: 45–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annice, M. 1956. “Logic and Mystery in the Quarta Via of St. Thomas.” Thomist 19: 22–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armour, L. 1980. “Ideas, Causes and God.” Sophia 19: 14–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. 1989. “C. B. Martin, Counterfactuals, Causality, and Conditionals.” In Heil, J. (ed.), Cause, Mind and Reality: Essays Honouring C. B. Martin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 7–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D., and McCall, S.. 1989. “God's Lottery.” Analysis 49: 223–4.Google Scholar
Austin, W. 1985. “Philo's Reversal.” Philosophical Topics 13: 103–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbour, I. 1966. Issues in Philosophy of Religion. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1972. The Ontological Argument. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrow, J., and Tipler, F.. 1986. The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baumer, W. 1969. “Kant on Cosmological Arguments.” In Beck, L. (ed.), Kant Studies Today. LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court.Google Scholar
Behe, M. 1996a. Darwin's Black Box. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Behe, M. 1996b. “Evidence for Intelligent Design from Biochemistry.” Http://www.discovery.org/crsc, accessed May 15, 2004.
Behe, M. 2001. “The Modern Intelligent Design Hypothesis: Breaking Rules.” Philosophia Christi 3: 165–79.Google Scholar
Benacerraf, P. 1962. “Tasks, Supertasks, and the Modern Eleatics.” Journal of Philosophy 59: 765–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergmann, M. 2001. “Sceptical Theism and Rowe's New Evidential Argument from Evil.” Nous 35, no. 2: 278–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berman, D. 1988. A History of Atheism in Britain: From Hobbes to Russell. London: CroomHelm.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. 1988. The Reality of Numbers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bobik, J. 1968. “The First Part of the Third Way.” Philosophical Studies (Ireland) 17: 142–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobik, J. 1972. “Further Reflections on the First Part of the Third Way.” Philosophical Studies (Ireland) 20: 166–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobik, J. 1987. “Aquinas' Fourth Way and the Approximating Relation.” Thomist 51: 17–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bostrom, N. 2002. Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. 1984. Evolution: The History of an Idea. Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Brady, J. 1974. “Note on the Fourth Way.” New Scholasticism 48: 219–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brecher, B. 1976. “Descartes' Causal Argument for the Existence of God.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7: 418–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewster, L. 1974. “How to Know Enough about the Unknown Faculty.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 12: 366–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bringsjord, S. 1986. “Swinburne's Argument from Consciousness.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 19: 127–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, G. 1984. “A Defence of Pascal's Wager.” Religious Studies 20: 465–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, P. 1965. “A Medieval Analysis of Infinity.” Journal for the History of Philosophy 3: 242–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R. 1982. “A Reply to Kelly on Aquinas' Third Way.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 13: 225–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burns, R. 1987. “Meynell's Arguments for the Intelligibility of the Universe.” Religious Studies 23: 183–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byl, J. 1994. “On Pascal's Wager and Infinite Utilities.” Faith and Philosophy 11: 467–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cahn, S. 1976. “Cacodaemony.” Analysis 37: 69–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, R. 1976. From Belief to Understanding. Canberra: ANU Press.Google Scholar
Caputo, J. 1974. “Kant's Refutation of the Cosmological Argument.” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 42: 686–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cargile, J. 1966. “Pascal's Wager.” Philosophy 41: 250–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. 1950. “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4. Reprinted in Carnap (1956).
Carnap, R. 1956. Meaning and Necessity, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Centore, F. 1980. “Camus, Pascal, and the Absurd.” New Scholasticism 54: 46–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chad, A. 1997. “The Principle of Sufficient Reason and the Uncaused Beginning of the Universe.” Dialogue 36: 555–62.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chambers, T. 2000. “On Behalf of the Devil: A Parody of St. Anselm Revisited.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 93–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charlesworth, M. 1965. St. Anselm's Proslogion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1979. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clack, B., and Clack, B.. 1998. The Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Polity.Google Scholar
Clarke, B. 1974. “The Argument from Design – A Piece of Abductive Reasoning.” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 5: 65–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, B. 1979. “The Argument from Design.” Sophia 18: 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, R. 1988. “Vicious Infinite Regress Arguments.” In Tomberlin (1988), 369–80.
Clatterbaugh, K. 1980. “Descartes' Causal Likeness Principle.” Philosophical Review 89: 379–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clayton, P. 1996. “The Theistic Argument from Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy.” International Philosophical Quarterly 36: 5–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, R. 1999. “The Fine-Tuning Design Argument: A Scientific Argument for the Existence of God.” In Murray, M. (ed.), Reason for the Hope Within. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 67–72.Google Scholar
Collins, R. 2003. “Evidence for Fine-Tuning.” In Manson, N. (ed.), God and Design. London: Routledge, 178–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connolly, T. 1954. “Basis for the Third Proof of the Existence of God.” Thomist 17: 281–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway, D. 1974. “Possibility and Infinite Time: A Logical Paradox in St. Thomas' Third Way.” International Philosophical Quarterly 14: 201–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway, D. 1983. “Concerning Infinite Chains, Infinite Trains, and Borrowing a Typewriter.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 14: 71–86.Google Scholar
Conway, D. 1984. “‘It Would Have Happened Already’: On One Argument for a First Cause.” Analysis 44: 159–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornman, J., and Lehrer, K.. 1968. Philosophical Problems and Arguments: An Introduction. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cox, H. 1974. “Composition and the Cosmological Argument: A Trivial Issue.” New Scholasticism 48: 365–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1979a. The Kalām Cosmological Argument. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1979b. “Whitrow, Popper, and the Impossibility of an Infinite Past.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30: 166–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1985. “Professor Mackie and the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 20: 367–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1988. “Quentin Smith on Infinity and the Past.” Philosophy of Science 55: 453–5.Google Scholar
Craig, W. 1991a. “The Kalām Cosmological Argument and the Hypothesis of a Quiescent Universe.” Faith and Philosophy 8: 104–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1991b. “Theism and Big Bang Cosmology.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 492–503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1991c. “Time and Infinity.” International Philosophical Quarterly 31: 387–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1992a. “God and the Initial Singularity.” Faith and Philosophy 9: 238–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1992b. “The Origin and Creation of the Universe: A Reply to Adolf Grünbaum.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43: 233–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1992c. “Philosophical and Scientific Pointers to Creation Ex Nihilo.” In Geivett, D. and Sweetman, B. (eds.), Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craig, W. 1993a. “The Caused Beginning of the Universe: A Response to Quentin Smith.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44: 623–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1993b. “Graham Oppy on the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Sophia 32: 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1994a. “A Response to Grünbaum on Creation and Big Bang Cosmology.” Philosophia Naturalis 31: 237–49.Google Scholar
Craig, W. 1994b. “Professor Grünbaum on CreationErkenntnis 40: 325–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1997a. “In Defence of the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Faith and Philosophy 14: 236–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1997b. “Hartle-Hawking Cosmology and Atheism.” Analysis 57: 291–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1998. “Theism and the Origin of the Universe.” Erkenntnis 48: 47–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 1999. “A Swift and Simple Refutation of the Kalām Cosmological Argument?Religious Studies 35: 57–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W. 2000. “Naturalism and Cosmology.” In Craig, W. and Moreland, J. (eds.), Naturalism: A Critical Analysis. London: Routledge, 215–52.Google Scholar
Craig, W. 2003a. “The Cosmological Argument.” In Copan, P. and Moser, P. (eds.), The Rationality of Theism. London: Routledge, 112–31.Google Scholar
Craig, W. 2003b. “Design and the Anthropic Fine-Tuning of the Universe.” In Manson, N. (ed.), God and Design. London: Routledge, 155–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, W., and McLeod, M., eds. 1990. Rational Theism: The Logic of a Worldview. Lewiston: N. Y. Edwin Mellen.Google Scholar
Craig, W., and Smith, Q.. 1993. Theism, Atheism and Big Bang Cosmology. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Crawford, P. 1981. “Is the Cosmological Argument Dependent upon the Ontological Argument?Sophia 20: 27–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dalton, P. 1975. “Pascal's Wager: The Second Argument.” Southern Journal of Religion 13: 31–46.Google Scholar
Dalton, P. 1976. “Pascal's Wager: The First Argument.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7: 346–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daniels, C. 1997. “God, Demon, Good, Evil.” Journal of Value Inquiry 31, no. 2: 177–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davey, K., and Clifton, R.. 2001. “Insufficient Reason and the ‘New Cosmological Argument’.” Religious Studies 37: 485–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, H. 1987. Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, B. 1993. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, J. 1987. “The Design Argument, Cosmic ‘Fine-Tuning’, and the Anthropic Principle.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 22: 139–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, S. 1997. God, Reason and Theistic Proofs. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1986. The Blind Watchmaker. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Day, T. 1987. “Aquinas on Infinite Regress.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 22: 151–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delahunty, R. 1980. “Descartes' Cosmological Argument.” Philosophical Quarterly 30: 34–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deltete, R. 1998. “Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists: A Reply to Quentin Smith.” Philosophy 73: 490–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deltete, R., and Guy, R.. 1997. “Hartle-Hawking Cosmology and Unconditional Probabilities.” Analysis 57: 304–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dembski, W. 1998. The Design Inference: Eliminating Chance through Small Probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dembski, W. 2002. No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot Be Purchased without Intelligence. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Devine, P. 1975. “The Perfect Island, the Devil, and Existent Unicorns.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 255–60.Google Scholar
Dewan, L. 1982. “The Distinctiveness of St. Thomas' ‘Third Way’.” Modern Schoolman 57: 201–18.Google Scholar
Dewan, L. 1991. “The Interpretation of St. Thomas's Third Way.” In Littera, sensus, sententia, Studi in onore del Prof. Clemente J. Vansteenkiste O. P., ed., Lobato, A., O. P. Milan: Massimo, 201–18.Google Scholar
Dilley, F. 1970. “Descartes' Cosmological Argument.” Monist 54: 427–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dilley, F. 1976. “Misunderstanding the Cosmological Argument of St. Thomas.” New Scholasticism 50: 96–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doolittle, R. 1997. “A Delicate Balance.” Boston Review (February/March): 28–9.Google Scholar
Doore, G. 1980. “The Argument from Design: Some Better Reasons for Agreeing with Hume.” Religious Studies 16: 145–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, P. 1997. “The Kalām Cosmological Argument.” In Pojman, L. (ed.), Philosophy of Religion, 3rd ed. Belmont: Wadsworth, 42–7.Google Scholar
Duerlinger, J. 1982. “Unspoken Connections in the Design Argument.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42: 519–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duff, A. 1986. “Pascal's Wager and Infinite Utilities.” Analysis 46: 107–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duncan, C. 2003. “Do Vague Probabilities Really Scotch Pascal's Wager?Philosophical Studies 112: 279–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dupré, L. 1972. “The Cosmological Argument after Kant.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3: 131–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durrant, M. 1969. “St. Thomas' Third Way.” Religious Studies 4: 229–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J. 1995. Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J., and J. Norton. 1996. “Infinite Pains: The Trouble with Supertasks.” In Morton, A. and Stich, S. (eds.), Benacerraf and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Edwards, R. 1968. “Composition and the Cosmological Argument.” Mind 78: 115–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, R. 1971. “The Validity of Aquinas' Third Way.” New Scholasticism 45: 117–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, R. 1973. “Another Visit to the Third Way.” New Scholasticism 47: 100–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E. 1988. “Quentin Smith on Infinity and the Past.” Philosophy of Science 55: 453–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliot, R., and Smith, M.. 1978. “Descartes, God and the Evil Spirit.” Sophia 17: 33–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fakhry, M. 1959. “The Classical Islamic Arguments for the Existence of God.” The Muslim World 49: 133–45.Google Scholar
Faricy, R. 1957. “Establishment of the Basic Principle of the Fifth Way.” New Scholasticism 31: 189–208.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J., ed. 1989. Reason and Responsibility, 7th ed. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Ferraiolo, W. 2000. “The Heaven Problem.” Southwest Philosophy Review 16: 75–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fetzer, J., ed. 1984. Principles of Philosophical Reasoning. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld.Google Scholar
Finili, A. 1954. “Recent Works in the Tertia Via.” Dominican Studies 7: 22–47.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B., Stephens, C., and Sober, E.. 1999. “How Not to Detect Design – Critical Notice: Dembski (1998).” Philosophy of Science 66: 472–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, F. 1981. “The Onus of Proof in Arguments about the Problem of Evil.” Religious Studies 17: 19–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flage, D., and Bonnen, C.. 1989. “Descartes' Factitious Ideas of God.” Modern Schoolman 66: 197–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flew, A. 1960. “Is Pascal's Wager the Only Safe Bet?” Rationalist Annual 76. Reprinted in Flew (1984).
Flew, A. 1984. God, Freedom and Immortality. Buffalo: Prometheus.Google Scholar
Flint, T. 1998. Divine Providence. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Forrest, P. 1982. “Occam's Razor and Possible Worlds.” Monist 65: 456–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. 1983. “Priest on the Argument for Design.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 84–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friquegnon, M. 1975. “God and Other Programs.” Religious Studies 15: 83–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaine, S. 2003. Will There Be Free Will in Heaven?London: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Gale, R. 1991. On the Nature and Existence of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gale, R. 1996. “Some Difficulties in Theistic Treatments of Evil.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 206–18.
Gale, R. 1998. “Review of Oppy, Ontological Arguments and Belief in God.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58: 715–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gale, R., and Pruss, A.. 1999. “A New Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 35: 461–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gale, R., and , A. Pruss. 2003. “A Response to Oppy, and to Davey and Clifton.” Religious Studies 38: 89–99.Google Scholar
Gaskin, J. 1976. “The Design Argument: Hume's Critique of Pure Reason.” Religious Studies 12: 331–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geanakoplos, J., and Sebenius, J.. 1983. “Don't Bet on It.” Journal of American Statistical Association 78: 424–6.Google Scholar
Gellman, J. 1994. “Experiencing God's Infinity.” American Philosophical Quarterly 31: 53–61.Google Scholar
Gillespie, N. 1979. Charles Darwin and the Problem of Creation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Glass, M., and Wolfe, J.. 1986. “Paley's Design Argument for God.” Sophia 25: 17–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goetz, S. 1989. “Craig's Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Faith and Philosophy 6: 99–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golding, J. 1994. “Pascal's Wager.” Modern Schoolman 71: 115–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, L. 1971. “Ghazālī's Argument from Creation.” International Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 2: 67–85, 168–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. 1993. Eight Little Piggies. New York: Norton, chapter 8: “Darwin and Paley Meet the Invisible Hand,” 138–52.Google Scholar
Grave, S. 1976. “Hume's Criticism of the Argument from Design.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 30: 64–78.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 1990. “The Pseudo-Problem of Creation in Physical Cosmology.” In Leslie, J. (ed.), Physical Cosmology and Philosophy. New York: Macmillan, 92–112.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 1991. “Creation as a Pseudo-Explanation in Current Physical Cosmology.” Erkenntnis 35: 233–54.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 1994. “Some Comments on William Craig's ‘Creation and Big Bang Cosmology’.” Philosophia Naturalis 31: 225–36.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 1996. “Theological Misinterpretations of Current Physical Cosmology.” Foundations of Physics 26: 523–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 2000. “A New Critique of Theological Interpretations of Physical Cosmology.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51: 1–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. 1972. “The Logic of Pascal's Wager.” American Philosophical Quarterly 9: 186–92.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1987. “The Inverse Gambler's Fallacy: The Argument from Design. The Anthropic Principle Applied to Wheeler's Universes.” Mind 76: 331–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. 2000. “Objecting Vaguely to Pascal's Wager.” Philosophical Studies 98: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. 2003. “Waging War on Pascal's Wager.” Philosophical Review 112: 27–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. 2004. “Pascal's Wager.” In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/pascal-wager, accessed June 15, 2004.Google Scholar
Haldane, J. 1983. “A Benign Regress.” Analysis 43: 115–16.Google Scholar
Hardy, A. 1975. The Biology of God. London: Cape.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986. Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press (Bradford Books).Google Scholar
Harris, W.. 1999. “A Randomised, Controlled Trial of the Effects of Remote, Intercessory Prayer on Outcomes of Patients Admitted to a Coronary Unit.” Archives of Internal Medicine 159: 2273–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, C. 1974. “Totalities and the Logic of First Cause Arguments.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35: 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, F. 1961. “Some Brief Remarks Concerning the Quinque Via of St. Thomas.” Franciscan Studies 21: 80–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazen, A. 1999. “On Gödel's Ontological Proof.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76, no. 3: 361–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hebblethwaite, B. 1986. “Mellor's ‘Bridge-Hand’ Argument.” Religious Studies 22: 473–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hick, J., 1970. Arguments for the Existence of God. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hinton, J. and Martin, C.. 1953/4. “Achilles and the Tortoise.” Analysis 14: 56–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holcomb, H. 1995. “To Bet the Impossible Bet.” International Journal of Philosophy of Religion 35: 65–79.Google Scholar
Holder, R. 2002. “Fine Tuning, Multiple Universes, and Theism.” Nous 36: 295–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hourani, G. 1958. “The Dialogue between Al Ghazālī and the Philosophers on the Origin of the World.” The Muslim World 48: 183–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D., ed. 1996a. The Evidential Argument from Evil. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D. 1996b. “Introduction.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), ⅺ–ⅹⅹ.
Howard-Snyder, D. 1996c. “The Argument from Inscrutable Evil.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 286–310.
Hughes, C. 1989. On a Complex Theory of a Simple God. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hughes, G. 1995. The Nature of God. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Humphrey, T. 1974. “How Descartes Avoids the Hidden Faculties Trap.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 12: 371–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurlbutt, R. 1965. Hume, Newton and the Design Argument. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
Immerwahr, J. 1982. “Descartes' Two Cosmological Proofs.” New Scholasticism 56: 346–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jack, H. 1964. “A Recent Attempt to Prove God's Existence.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25: 575–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1995. From Metaphysics to Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Jordan, J. 1991a. “Duff and the Wager.” Analysis 51: 174–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, J. 1991b. “The Many-Gods Objection and Pascal's Wager.” International Philosophical Quarterly 31: 309–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, J. 1993a. “Pascal's Wager and the Problem of Infinite Utilities.” Faith and Philosophy 10: 49–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, J. 1993b. “Pascal's Wager and the Rationality of Devotion to God.” Faith and Philosophy 10: 49–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, J., ed. 1994a. Gambling on God: Essays on Pascal's Wager. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Jordan, J. 1994b. “The St. Petersburg Paradox and Pascal's Wager.” Philosophia 23: 207–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, B. 1997. “The Cosmological Argument without the Principle of Sufficient Reason.” Faith and Philosophy 14: 62–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, C. 1981. “Some Fallacies in the First Movement of Aquinas' Third Way.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12: 39–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, C. 1982. “The Third Way and the Possible Eternity of the World.” New Scholasticism 56: 273–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. 1968. “The Idea of God.” In Descartes: A Study of His Philosophy. New York: Random House, 126–45.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1969. The Five Ways: St. Thomas Aquinas' Proofs of God's Existence. New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
King-Farlow, J. 1975. “The First Way in Physical and Moral Space.” Thomist 39: 349–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knasas, J. 1978. “‘Necessity’ in the Tertia Via.” New Scholasticism 52: 373–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knasas, J. 1980. “Making Sense of the Tertia Via.” New Scholasticism 54: 476–511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kondoleon, T. 1980. “The Third Way: Encore.” Thomist 44: 325–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koons, R. 1997. “A New Look at the Cosmological Argument.” American Philosophical Quarterly 34: 193–211.Google Scholar
Koons, R. 2001. “Defeasible Reasoning, Special Pleading and the Cosmological Argument: A Reply to Oppy.” Faith and Philosophy 18: 192–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kragh, H. 1996. Cosmology and Controversy: The Historical Development fo Two Theories of the Universe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kretzmann, N., ed. 1982. Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. 1997. “Heaven and Hell”. In Quinn, P. and Taliaferro, C. (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Blackwell, 562–8.Google Scholar
Kwang, C., Wirth, D., and Lobo, R.. 2001. “Does Prayer Influence the Success of in Vitro Fertilisation Transfer? Report of a Masked, Randomised Trial.” Journal of Reproductive Medicine 46: 781–7.Google Scholar
Croix, R. 1972. Proslogion II and III: A Third Interpretation of Anselm's Argument. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Landsberg, P. 1971. “Gambling on God.” Mind 80: 100–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langtry, B. 1999. “Review of Oppy, Ontological Arguments and Belief in God.” Sophia 36: 147–50.Google Scholar
Lavine, S. 1994. Understanding the Infinite. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. 1985. “Modern Cosmology and the Creation of Life.” In McMullin, E. (ed.), Evolution and Creation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 91–120.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. 1989. Universes. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Leslie, J., ed. 1990. Physical Cosmology and Philosophy. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1970. “Anselm and Actuality.” Nous 4: 175–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1976. “Survival and Identity.” In Rorty, A. (ed.), The Identities of Persons. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 17–40.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1999. Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linehan, J. 1959. “Modern Science and the Proof from Motion of the Existence of a Theistic God.” Franciscan Studies 19: 128–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorca, D. 1995. “A Critique of Quentin Smith's Atheistic Argument from Big Bang Cosmology.” Philosophy 70: 39–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W., and G. Schlesinger. 1989. “You Bet Your Life.” In Feinberg (1989), 82–90.
Mabey, R. 1971. “Confusion and the Cosmological Argument.” Mind 80: 124–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntosh, D. 1994. “Could God Have Made the Big Bang? (On Theistic Counterfactuals).” Dialogue 33: 3–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntosh, J. 2000. “Is Pascal's Wager Self-Defeating?.” Sophia 39: 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. 1955. “Evil and Omnipotence.” Mind 64: 200–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. 1982. The Miracle of Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Madden, E., and Hare, P.. 1968. Evil and the Concept of God. Springfield, Ill.: C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Makinde, M. 1985. “Pascal's Wager and the Atheist's Dilemma.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 17: 115–29.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1960. “Anselm's Ontological Arguments.” Philosophical Review 69: 41–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, W. 1972. “The Ontological Presuppositions of the Ontological Argument.” Review of Metaphysics 26: 260–77.Google Scholar
Manson, N. 2000a. “Anthropocentrism and the Design Argument.” Religious Studies 36: 163–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manson, N. 2000b. “There Is No Adequate Definition of ‘Fine-Tuned for Life’.” Inquiry 43: 341–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manson, N., ed. 2003. God and Design. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manson, N., and Thrush, M.. 2003. “Fine-Tuning, Multiple Universes and the ‘This Universe’ Objection.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84: 67–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markosian, N. 1995. “On the Argument from Quantum Cosmology against Theism.” Analysis 55: 247–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmura, M. 1957. “The Logical Role of the Argument from Time in the Tahāfut's Second Proof for the World's Pre-Eternity.” The Muslim World 47: 306–14.Google Scholar
Martin, C. 1959. Religious Belief. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, M. 1975. “On Four Critiques of Pascal's Wager.” Sophia 14: 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M. 1983. “Pascal's Wager as an Argument for Not Believing in God.” Religious Studies 19: 57–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M. 1990. Atheism: A Philosophical Justification. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, M. 1997. “Problems with Heaven.” Http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/michael_martin/heaven.html, accessed June 29, 2004.
Matson, M. 1965. The Existence of God. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mautner, T. 1969. “Aquinas' Third Way.” American Philosophical Quarterly 6: 298–304.Google Scholar
McClelland, R., and Deltete, R.. 2000. “Divine Causation.” Faith and Philosophy 17: 3–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrew, T., McGrew, L., and Vestrup, E.. 2001. “Probabilities and the Fine-Tuning Argument: A Sceptical View.” Mind 110: 127–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, R. 1984. “Necessary Agnosticism?Analysis 44: 198–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, T. 1957. “The Argument from Design.” Philosophy 32: 219–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, T. 1972. The Argument from Design. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McQuinn, J. 1978. “The Third Way to God: A New Approach.” Thomist 42: 50–68.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. 1973. “God and Probability.” In Yandell, K. (ed.), God, Man and Religion. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Meyer, R. 1987. “God Exists!Nous 21: 345–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miethe, T. 1979. “The Cosmological Argument: A Research Bibliography.” New Scholasticism 53: 285–305.Google Scholar
Miller, K. 1999. Finding Darwin's God: A Scientist's Search for Common Ground between God and Evolution. New York: Cliff Street Books.Google Scholar
Miller, K. 2003. “Answering the Biochemical Argument from Design.” In Manson, N. (ed.), God and Design. London: Routledge, 292–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monk, N. 1997. “Conceptions of Space-Time: Problems and Possible Solutions.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28, no. 1: 1–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moody, T. 1996. Does God Exist?Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. 2003. “A Response to a Platonistic and to a Set-Theoretic Objection to the Kalam Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 39: 373–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morreall, J. 1979. “Aquinas' Fourth Way.” Sophia 18: 20–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, T. 1986. “Pascalian Wagering.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16: 437–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, W. 1999. “Must the Past Have a Beginning?.” Philo 2: 5–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, W. 2002a. “Craig on the Actual Infinite.” Religious Studies 38: 147–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, W. 2002b. “Creation Ex Nihilo and the Big Bang.” Philo 5: 23–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mougin, G., and Sober, E.. 1994. “Betting against Pascal's Wager.” Nous 27: 382–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Y., Oppy, G., and Trakakis, N.. 2004. “Salvation in Heaven?Philosophical Papers 33: 1, 97–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narveson, J. 1965. “On a New Argument from Design.” Journal of Philosophy 62: 223–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Natoli, C. 1983. “The Role of the Wager in Pascal's Apologetics.” New Scholasticism 57: 98–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, H. 1993. “Kant on Arguments Cosmological and Ontological.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67: 167–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, K. 1978. “Evolution and the Argument from Design.” Religious Studies 14: 423–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
New, C. 1993. “Antitheism.” Ratio 6: 36–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newman, J. 1870. An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent. Oxford: Clarendon, 72–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nicholl, L. 1979. “Pascal's Wager: The Bet Is Off.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39: 274–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, D. 1968. “Descartes on Unknown Faculties: An Essential Inconsistency.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 6: 245–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, D. 1974. “Descartes' Inconsistency: A Reply.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 12: 509–20.Google Scholar
Norton, D. 1978. “A Reply to Professor Stevens.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 16: 338–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noxon, J. 1964. “Hume's Agnosticism.” Philosophical Review 73: 248–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Briant, W. 1967. “A New Argument from Design?Sophia 6: 30–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Briant, W. 1979. “Is Descartes' Evil Spirit Finite or Infinite?Sophia 18: 28–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oderberg, D. 2002a. “Traversal of the Infinite, the ‘Big Bang’, and the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Philosophia Christi 4, no. 2: 303–34.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. 2002b. “The Tristram Shandy Paradox: A Reply to Graham Oppy.” Philosophia Christi 4, no. 2: 351–60.Google Scholar
O'Donoghue, D. 1953. “Analysis of the Tertia Via of St. Thomas.” Irish Theological Quarterly 20: 129–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Donoghue, D. 1969. “The First Part of the Third Way: Reply.” Philosophical Studies (Ireland) 18: 172–7.Google Scholar
Olding, A. 1971. “The Argument from Design – A Reply to R. G. Swinburne.” Religious Studies 7: 361–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olding, A. 1973. “Design – A Further Reply to R. G. Swinburne.” Religious Studies 9: 229–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Leary-Hawthorne, J., and Cortens, A.. 1995. “Towards Ontological Nihilism.” Philosophical Studies 79, no. 2: 143–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppenheimer, P., and E. Zalta. 1991. “On the Logic of the Ontological Argument.” In Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 5: The Philosophy of Religion. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview, 509–29.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 1990. “On Rescher on Pascal's Wager.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 30: 159–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1991. “Craig, Mackie and the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 27: 189–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1994. “Weak Agnosticism Defended.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 36: 147–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1995a. “Inverse Operations with Transfinite Numbers and the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” International Philosophical Quarterly 35, no. 2: 219–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1995b. “Kalām Cosmological Arguments: Reply to Professor Craig.” Sophia 34: 15–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1995c. Ontological Arguments and Belief in God. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 1995d. “Professor William Craig's Criticisms of Critiques of Kalām Cosmological Arguments by Paul Davies, Stephen Hawking, and Adolf Grünbaum.” Faith and Philosophy 12: 237–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1996a. “Gödelian Ontological Arguments.” Analysis 56, no. 4 (October) 1: 226–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1996b. “Hume and the Argument for Biological Design.” Biology and Philosophy 11: 519–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1996c. “Ontological Arguments.” Stanford Electronic Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ontological-arguments (revised 2002). Accessed March 2, 2004.
Oppy, G. 1996d. “Pascal's Wager Is a Possible Bet (But Not a Very Good One): Reply to Harmon Holcomb III.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 40: 101–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1996e. “Review of W. Craig and Q. Smith, Theism, Atheism and Big Bang Cosmology.” Faith and Philosophy 13: 125–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1997a. “Countable Fusion Not Yet Proven Guilty: It May Be the Whiteheadian Account of Space Whatdunnit.” Analysis 57, no. 4: 249–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1997b. “Pantheism, Quantification, and Mereology.” Monist 80, no. 2: 320–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1997c. “Some Questions about ‘The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology’.” Sophia 36, no. 1: 84–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 1999. “Koons' Cosmological Argument.” Faith and Philosophy 16: 378–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2000a. “Humean Supervenience?Philosophical Studies 101, no. 1: 75–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2000b. “On ‘A New Cosmological Argument’.” Religious Studies 36: 345–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2000c. “Response to Gettings.” Analysis 60: 363–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2001a. “Reply to Langtry.” Sophia 40: 73–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2001b. “Time, Successive Addition, and the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Philosophia Christi 3: 181–91.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 2002a. “Arguing about the Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Philo 5, no. 1: 34–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2002b. “More Than a Flesh Wound: Reply to Oderberg.” Ars Disputandi 2: 1–11. Http://www.ArsDisputandi.org.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2002c. “Paley's Argument for Design.” Philo 5, no. 2: 41–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2002d. “The Tristram Shandy Paradox: A Response to David S. Oderberg.” Philosophia Christi 4, no. 2: 335–49.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 2003a. “From the Tristram Shandy Paradox to the Christmas Shandy Paradox: Reply to Oderberg.” Ars Disputandi 3: 1–24. Http://www.ArsDisputandi.org.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 2004a. “Arguments from Moral Evil.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 56: 59–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2004b. “Faulty Reasoning about Default Principles in Cosmological Arguments.” Faith and Philosophy 21, no. 2: 242–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2004c. “God, God* and God′.” In Fisher, A. and Ramsay, H. (eds.), Faith and Reason: Friends or Foes in the New Millennium? Hindmarsh: ATF Press, 171–86.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 2004d. “Review of God and Design, edited by Neil Manson.” Sophia 43, no. 1: 127–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. 2006. Philosophical Perspectives on Infinity. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, G. In preparation. Describing Gods. Unpublished ms.
Owens, J. 1952/3. “Conclusion of the Prima Via.” Modern Schoolman 30: 33–53, 109–21, 203–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, J. 1971. “‘Cause of Necessity’ in Aquinas' Tertia Via.” Medieval Studies 33: 21–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, J. 1974. “Aquinas and the Five Ways.” Monist 58: 16–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, J. 1980. “‘Quandoque’ and ‘Aliquando’ in Aquinas' Tertia Via.” New Scholasticism 54: 447–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paley, W. 1890/1805. Natural Theology. London: Gilbert and Rivington.Google Scholar
Parent, W. 1976. “Philo's Confession.” Philosophical Quarterly 26: 63–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Paul, G. 2005. “Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies.” Journal of Religion and Society 7: 1–17.Google Scholar
Pearl, L. 1970. “Hume's Criticism of the Argument from Design.” Monist 54: 270–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penelhum, T. 1964. “Pascal's Wager.” Journal of Religion 44: 32–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1967. God and Other Minds. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1979a. “Is Belief in God Rational?” In Delaney, C. (ed.), Rationality and Religious Belief. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2–29.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1979b. “The Probabilistic Argument from Evil.” Philosophical Studies 35: 1–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1980. Does God Have a Nature?Milwaukee, Minn.: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1983. “Reason and Belief in God.” In Plantinga, A. and Wolterstorff, N. (eds.), Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1988/96. “Epistemic Probability.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 69–96.
Pomerlau, W. 1985. “Does Reason Demand That God Be Infinite?Sophia 24: 18–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prado, C. 1971. “The Third Way Revisited.” New Scholasticism 45: 495–501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prevost, R. 1990. “Classical Theism and the Kalam Principle.” In Craig, W. and McLeod, M. (eds.), Rational Theism: The Logic of a Worldview. Lewiston, N.Y.: Edwin Mellen, 113–25.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1988. “Review of Change in View.” Philosophical Books 29: 38–41.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1992. “Metaphysical Pluralism.” Journal of Philosophy 89, no. 8: 387–409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. 1981. “The Argument from Design.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59: 422–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. 1953. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quinn, J. 1978. “The Third Way to God: A New Approach.” Thomist 42: 50–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, J. 1982. “A Few Reflections on ‘The Third Way: Encore’.” Thomist 46: 75–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rashdall, H. 1907. “The Moral Argument for the Existence of God.” Reprinted in Hick, J. (ed.) (1964), Classical and Contemporary Readings in the Philosophy of Religion. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 268–73.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, B. 1972. The Cosmological Argument: A ReassessmentSpringfield, Ill.: Charles C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Remnant, P. 1959. “Kant and the Cosmological Argument.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 37: 152–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rescher, N. 1985. Pascal's Wager. South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Ross, J. 1969. Philosophical Theology. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. 1975. The Cosmological Argument. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. 1979. “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism.” American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 335–41.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. 1984. “Rationalistic Theology and Some Principles of Explanation.” Faith and Philosophy 1: 357–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowe, W. 1986. “Evil and the Theistic Hypothesis.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16: 95–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowe, W. 1988. “Response to Dicker.” Faith and Philosophy 5: 203–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowe, W. 1991. “Ruminations about Evil.” Noûs, supp. 5: 69–88.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. 1995. “Religion within the Bounds of Naturalism.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 38: 17–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowe, W. 1996. “The Evidential Argument from Evil: A Second Look.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 262–85.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. 2001. “Sceptical Theism: A Response to Bergmann.” Noûs 35: 297–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. 1977. “William Whewell and the Argument for Design.” Monist 54: 244–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. 1979. The Darwinian Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. 2003. “Modern Biologists and the Argument from Design.” In Manson, N. (ed.), God and Design. London: Routledge, 308–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Lord B. 1927. “Why I Am Not a Christian.” Rationalist Press Association Ltd. London: Watts and Co.
Russell, B. 1989. “The Persistent Problem of Evil.” Faith and Philosophy 6: 121–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1996. “Defenceless.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 193–205.
Ryan, J. 1945. “The Wager in Pascal and Others.” New Scholasticism 19: 233–50. Reprinted in Jordan (1994b).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadowsky, J. 1988. “Did Darwin Destroy the Design Argument?International Philosophical Quarterly 28: 95–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salamucha, J. 1958. “The Proof ‘Ex Motu’ for the Existence of God: Logical Analysis of St. Thomas' Arguments.” New Scholasticism 32: 334–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. 1978. “Religion and Science: A New Look at Hume's Dialogues.” Philosophical Studies 33: 143–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sanford, D. 1967. “Degrees of Perfection, Argument for the Existence of God.” In Edwards, P. (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan, 324–6.Google Scholar
Schindler, D. 2002. “Freedom beyond Our Choosing: Augustine on the Will and Its Objects.” Communio: International Catholic Review 29: 4–12.Google Scholar
Schlesinger, G. 1973. “Probabilistic Arguments for Divine Design.” Philosophia 3: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlesinger, G. 1983. “Theism and Confirmation.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 46–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schoen, E. 1990. “The Sensory Presentation of Divine Infinity.” Faith and Philosophy 7: 3–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sennett, J. 1999. “Is There Freedom in Heaven?Faith and Philosophy 16: 69–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1874. The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Smart, J. 1955. “The Existence of God.” In Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A. (eds.), New Essays in Philosophical Theology. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Smith, Q. 1985. “Kant and the Beginning of the World.” New Scholasticism 59: 339–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1987. “Infinity and the Past.” Philosophy of Science 54: 63–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1988. “The Uncaused Beginning of the Universe.” Philosophy of Science 55: 39–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1991. “Atheism, Theism and Big Bang Cosmology.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 48–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1993a. “A Defence of the Cosmological Argument for God's Non-Existence.” In Craig, W. and Smith, Q., Theism, Atheism and Big Bang Cosmology. Oxford: Clarendon, 232–55.Google Scholar
Smith, Q. 1993b. “The Concept of a Cause of the Universe.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23: 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1993c. “Reply to Craig: The Possible Infinitude of the Past.” International Philosophical Quarterly 33: 109–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1994a. “Did the Big Bang Have a Cause?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 649–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1994b. “Stephen Hawking's Cosmology and Theism.” Analysis 54: 236–43.Google Scholar
Smith, Q. 1995a. “A Defence of a Principle of Sufficient Reason.” Metaphilosophy 26: 97–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1995b. “Internal and External Causal Explanation of the Universe.” Philosophical Studies 79: 283–310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1997a. “Quantum Cosmology's Implication of Atheism.” Analysis 57: 295–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1997b. “Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists.” Philosophy 72: 125–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 1999. “The Reason the Universe Exists Is That It Caused Itself to Exist.” Philosophy 74: 579–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Q. 2000. “Problem's with John Earman's Attempt to Reconcile Theism with General Relativity.” Erkenntnis 52: 1–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, J. 1987. “Gödel's Ontological Proof.” In Thomson, J. J. (ed.), On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 241–61.Google Scholar
Sobel, J. 1996. “Pascalian Wagers.” Synthese 108: 11–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, J. 2004. Logic and Theism. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 1993. The Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, Colo.: Westview.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 2003. “The Design Argument.” In Manson, N. (ed.), God and Design. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solon, T. 1973. “The Logic of Aquinas' Tertia Via.” Mind 82: 598–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1983. Time, Creation and the Continuum. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Stainsby, H. 1967. “Descartes' Argument for God.” Sophia 6: 11–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, E. 1990. “God, the Demon, and the Status of Theologies.” American Philosophical Quarterly 27: 163–7.Google Scholar
Stevens, J. 1978. “Unknown Faculties and Descartes' First Proof of the Existence of God.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 16: 334–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. 1983. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case against Belief. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stump, E. 1999. “The Problem of Evil.” Faith and Philosophy 2: 392–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, T. 1990. “Coming to Be without a Cause.” Philosophy 65: 261–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, T. 1994. “On the Alleged Causeless Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Quentin Smith.” Dialogue 33: 325–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sweeney, E. 1993. “Thomas Aquinas' Double Metaphysics of Simplicity and Infinity.” International Philosophical Quarterly 33: 297–317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1966. “The Beginning of the Universe.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 40: 125–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1968. “The Argument from Design.” Philosophy 43: 199–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1969. “The Christian Wager.” Religious Studies 4: 217–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1972. “The Argument from Design – A Defence.” Religious Studies 8: 193–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1977. The Coherence of Theism. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1979. The Existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1983. “A Theodicy of Heaven and Hell.” In Freddoso, A. (ed.), The Existence and Nature of God. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1994. The Christian God. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1996. Is There a God?Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taliaferro, C. 1992. “Imaginary Evil: A Sceptic's Wager.” Philosophia 21: 221–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taliaferro, C. 1998. Contemporary Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Taylor, J. 1997. “Kalām: A Swift Argument from Origins to a First Cause?Religious Studies 33: 167–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, R. 1963. Metaphysics. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Tennant, F. 1969. Philosophical Theology, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tomberlin, J., ed. 1988. Philosophical Perspectives 2. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Tooley, M. 1970. “Does the Cosmological Argument Entail the Ontological Argument?Monist 54: 416–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooley, M. 1981. “Plantinga's Defence of the Ontological Argument.” Mind 90: 422–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, M. 1968. “Deciding for God – the Bayesian Support of Pascal's Wager.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29: 84–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urban, L. 1984. “Understanding St. Thomas' Fourth Way.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 281–95.Google Scholar
Fraassen, B. 1995. “‘World’ Is Not a Count Noun.” Nous 29, no. 2: 139–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1991/6. “The Problem of Evil, the Problem of Air, and the Problem of Silence.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 151–74.
Wainwright, W. 1982. “Critical Notice of The Kalām Cosmological Argument.” Nous 16: 328–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, W. 1956. “Newtonian Antinomies against the Prima Via.” Thomist 19: 151–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, W. 1975. “The First Way: A Rejoinder.” Thomist 39: 375–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walls, J. 2002. Heaven: The Logic of Eternal Joy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. 2000. “Fine-Tuning and Multiple Universes.” Nous 34: 260–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 1978. “God.” In Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 130–62.Google Scholar
Wilson, P. 1991. “What Is the Explanandum of the Anthropic Principle?American Philosophical Quarterly 28: 167–73.Google Scholar
Wolfson, H. 1966. “Patristic Arguments against the Eternity of the World.” Harvard Theological Review 59: 354–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfson, H. 1976. The Philosophy of the Kalām. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, N. 1983. “Can Belief in God Be Rational If It Has No Foundations?” In Plantinga, A. and Wolterstorff, N. (eds.), Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Wright, T. 1951. “Necessary and Contingent Being in St. Thomas.” New Scholasticism 25: 439–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wykstra, S. 1984. “The Humean Obstacle to Evidential Arguments from Suffering: On Avoiding the Evils of ‘Appearance’.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16: 73–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wykstra, S. 1996. “Rowe's Noseeum Arguments from Evil.” In Howard-Snyder (1996a), 126–50.
Yarvin, H. 1976. “The Will to Come Out All Right.” Religious Studies 12: 303–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Graham Oppy, Monash University, Victoria
  • Book: Arguing about Gods
  • Online publication: 18 August 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498978.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Graham Oppy, Monash University, Victoria
  • Book: Arguing about Gods
  • Online publication: 18 August 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498978.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Graham Oppy, Monash University, Victoria
  • Book: Arguing about Gods
  • Online publication: 18 August 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498978.011
Available formats
×