Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T16:03:43.823Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2018

Kelly Sorensen
Affiliation:
Ursinus College, Pennsylvania
Diane Williamson
Affiliation:
Syracuse University, New York
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, Henry E. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, Henry E. Kant’s Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry E. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Altman, Matthew C., ed. The Palgrave Kant Handbook. London: Palgrave Macmillan, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Ameriks, Karl. Interpreting Kant’s Critiques. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Ameriks, Karl. Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. “Emotions in Kant’s Later Moral Philosophy: Honour and the Phenomenology of Moral Value.” In Kant’s Ethics of Virtue, edited by Betzler, Monika, 123–46. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2008.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. “Moral Bias and Corrective Practices: A Pragmatist Perspective.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 89 (2015): 2147.Google Scholar
Anderson-Gold, Sharon. “Privacy, Respect and the Virtues of Reticence in Kant.” Kantian Review 15, no. 2 (July 2010): 2842.Google Scholar
Aquila, Richard E.Is Sensation the Matter of Appearances?” In Interpreting Kant, edited by Gram, Moltke S., 1129. Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Aquila, Richard E.A New Look at Kant’s Aesthetic Judgment.” In Essays in Kant’s Aesthetics, edited by Cohen, Ted and Guyer, Paul, 87114. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Irwin, Terence. 2nd ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1999.Google Scholar
Ashfield, Andrew, and de Bolla, Peter, eds. The Sublime: A Reader in British Eighteenth-Century Aesthetic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banham, Gary. Kant’s Practical Philosophy: From Critique to Doctrine. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia. Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia. “Kantian Ethics and the Claims of Detachment.” In Feminist Interpretations of Immanuel Kant, edited by Schott, Robin May, 145–72. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia. “Love and Respect in the Doctrine of Virtue.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays, edited by Timmons, Mark, 391407. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, Lewis White. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.Google Scholar
Beck, Lewis White. Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969.Google Scholar
Betzler, Monika, ed. Kant’s Ethics of Virtue. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2008.Google Scholar
Borchardt, Frank L.Petrarch: The German Connection.” Studies in Romance Languages 3 (1975): 418–31.Google Scholar
Borges, Maria. “Physiology and the Controlling of Affects in Kant’s Philosophy.” Kantian Review 13, no. 2 (2008): 4666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, Emily. The Sublime in Modern Philosophy: Aesthetics, Ethics, and Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.Google Scholar
Brandt, Reinhard. “The Deductions in the Critique of Judgment.” In Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, edited by Forster, Eckhart, 177–91. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Breitenbach, Angela. “Understanding, Knowledge, and the Touchstone of Truth.” In Proceedings of the 12th International Kant Congress, edited by Violetta L. Waibel and Margit Ruffing. Berlin: de Gruyter, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Broadie, Alexander, and Pybus, Elizabeth M.. “Kant and Direct Duties.” Dialogue 20, no. 1 (1981): 6067.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Budd, Malcolm. The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.Google Scholar
Bunch, Aaron. “Throwing Oneself Away: Kant on the Forfeiture of Respect.” Kantian Review 19, no. 1 (March 2014): 7191.Google Scholar
Burke, Edmund. “A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful (1759).” In The Sublime: A Reader in British Eighteenth-Century Aesthetic Theory, edited by Ashfield, Andrew and de Bolla, Peter, 131–43. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Cassirer, Ernest, Kristeller, Paul Oskar, and Randall, John Herman Jr., eds. The Renaissance Philosophy of Man: Petrarca, Valla, Ficino, Pico, Pomponazzi, Vives. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948.Google Scholar
Chignell, Andrew. “Belief in Kant.” Philosophical Review 116, no. 3 (2007): 323–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chignell, Andrew. “Rational Hope, Moral Order, and the Revolution of the Will.” In Divine Order, Human Order, and the Order of Nature, edited by Watkins, Eric, 197218. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clewis, Robert R. The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.Google Scholar
Clewis, Robert R.The Place of the Sublime in Kant’s Project.” Studi Kantiani 28 (2015): 149–68.Google Scholar
Clewis, Robert R.A Theory of the Sublime Is Possible.” Wassard Elea Revista 4 (2016): 4568.Google Scholar
Clewis, Robert R.What’s the Big Idea? On Emily Brady’s Sublime.” The Journal of Aesthetic Education 50, no. 2 (2016): 104–18.Google Scholar
Clewis, Robert R. ed. Reading Kant’s Lectures. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Alix. “From Faking It to Making It: The Feeling of Love of Honor as an Aid to Morality.” In Reading Kant’s Lectures, edited by Clewis, Robert R., 243–56. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2015.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix. Kant and the Human Sciences: Biology, Anthropology, and History. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix. “Kant on Doxastic Voluntarism and Its Implications for the Ethics of Belief.” Kant Yearbook 5 (2013): 3350.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix. “Kant on Emotions, Feelings and Affectivity.” In The Palgrave Kant Handbook, edited by Matthew C. Altman. London: Palgrave Macmillan, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix. “The Ultimate Kantian Experience: Kant on Dinner Parties.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 25, no. 4 (2008): 315–36.Google Scholar
Cohen, Alix. ed. Kant on Emotion and Value. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Ted, and Guyer, Paul, eds. Essays in Kant’s Aesthetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.Google Scholar
Cooper, Anthony Ashley (3rd Earl of Shaftesbury). “A Letter concerning Enthusiasm.” In Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, edited by Robertson, John M., 542. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964.Google Scholar
Costelloe, Timothy M. The Sublime: From Antiquity to the Present. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.Google Scholar
Cranor, Carl. “Toward a Theory of Respect for Persons.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (October 1975): 303–19.Google Scholar
Crowther, Paul. The Kantian Sublime: From Morality to Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. “Kant on Respect, Dignity, and the Duty of Respect.” In Kant’s Ethics of Virtue, edited by Betzler, Monika, 175200. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2008.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. “Two Kinds of Respect.” Ethics 88, no. 1 (October 1977): 3649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deimling, Wiebke. “Kant’s Pragmatic Concept of Emotions.” In Kant on Emotion and Value, edited by Cohen, Alix, 108–25. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014.Google Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina. Kant and the Culture of Enlightenment. Albany: SUNY Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina. “The Pleasures of Contra-purposiveness: Kant, the Sublime and Being Human.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72, no. 1 (2014): 2535.Google Scholar
Deligiorgi, Katerina. The Scope of Autonomy: Kant and the Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denis, Lara. “Autonomy and the Highest Good.” Kantian Review 10, no. 1 (2005): 3359.Google Scholar
Denis, Lara. ed. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Denis, Lara, and Sensen, Oliver, eds. Kant’s Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. Freedom Evolves. New York: Penguin, 2004.Google Scholar
Descartes, René.Rules for the Direction of the Mind.” In The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol. 1, translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, 9–77. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.Google Scholar
DeWitt, Janelle. “Respect for the Moral Law: The Emotional Side of Reason.” Philosophy 89, no. 1 (2014): 3162.Google Scholar
Dillon, Robin S.How to Lose Your Self-Respect.” American Philosophical Quarterly 29, no. 2 (April 1992): 125–39.Google Scholar
Doran, Robert. The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Du Bos, Jean-Baptiste. Critical Reflections on Poetry, Painting, and Music. Translated by Nugent, Thomas. 3 Vols. London: John Nourse, 1748.Google Scholar
Düsing, Klaus. “Beauty as the Transition from Nature to Freedom in Kant’s Critique of Judgment.” Noûs 24, no. 1 (March 1990): 7992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyck, Corey W. Kant and Rational Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Ebels-Duggan, Kyla. “The Right and the Good, and the Threat of Despair: (Kantian) Ethics and the Need for Hope in God.” In Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 7, edited by Kvanvig, Jonathan L., 81109. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effron, Daniel A., and Conway, Paul. “When Virtue Leads to Villainy: Advances in Research on Moral Self-Licensing.” Current Opinions in Psychology 6 (2015): 3235.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen. “The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant’s Moral Theory.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, no. 4 (1992): 747–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esser, Andrea. Eine Ethik für Endliche, Kant’s Tugendlehre in der Gegenwart. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 2004.Google Scholar
Fahmy, Melissa Seymour. “Active Sympathetic Participation: Reconsidering Kant’s Duty of Sympathy.” Kantian Review 14, no. 1 (2009): 3152.Google Scholar
Fahmy, Melissa Seymour. “Understanding Kant’s Duty of Respect as a Duty of Virtue.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 10, no. 6 (2013): 723–40.Google Scholar
Falkenstein, Lorne. “Was Kant a Nativist?Journal of the History of Ideas 51, no. 4 (1990): 573–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fenves, Peter, ed. Raising the Tone of Philosophy: Late Essays by Immanuel Kant, Transformative Critique by Jacques Derrida. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Ferrarin, Alfredo. The Powers of Pure Reason: Kant and the Idea of Cosmic Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. System of Ethics. Translated by Breazeale, Daniel and Zöller, Günter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Sämmtliche Werke. Edited by Fichte, I. H. (1845–1846). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1971.Google Scholar
Flikschuh, Katrin. “Hope as Prudence: Practical Faith in Kant’s Political Thinking.” In Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus/ International Yearbook of German Idealism, Vol. 7, edited by Rush, Fred, Stolzenberg, Jürgen, Franks, Paul W., and Ulrichs, Lars-Thade, 95117 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2009).Google Scholar
Formosa, Paul. “Dignity and Respect: How to Apply Kant’s Formula of Humanity.” Philosophical Forum 45, no. 1 (Spring 2014): 4968.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forsey, Jane. “Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible?The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65, no. 4 (2007): 381–89.Google Scholar
Forster, Eckhart. Kant’s Transcendental Deductions. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Frierson, Patrick R. Freedom and Anthropology in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Frierson, Patrick R.Kantian Feeling: Empirical Psychology, Transcendental Critique, and Phenomenology.” Con-textos Kantianos no. 3 (2016): 353–71.Google Scholar
Frierson, Patrick R. Kant’s Empirical Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. New York: Continuum, 1989.Google Scholar
Gasché, Rodolphe. The Idea of Form: Rethinking Kant’s Aesthetics. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Geiger, Ido. “Is the Assumption of a Systematic Whole of Empirical Concepts a Necessary Condition of Knowledge?Kant-Studien 94, no. 3 (2003): 273–98.Google Scholar
Geiger, Ido. “Rational Feelings and Moral Agency.” Kantian Review 16, no. 2 (June 2011): 283308.Google Scholar
George, Rolf. “Kant’s Sensationism.” Synthese 47 (1981): 229–55.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Aesthetic Judging and the Intentionality of Pleasure.” Inquiry 46 (2003): 164–81.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Kant’s Aesthetics and Teleology.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, February 13, 2013. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/kant-aesthetics.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. The Normativity of Nature: Essays on Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Reflective Judgment and Taste.” Noûs 24, no. 1 (1990): 6378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition. New York: Garland Publishing, 1990.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. “Why Must We Presuppose the Systematicity of Nature?” In Kant and the Laws of Nature, edited by Michela Massimi and Angela Breitenbach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Goy, Ina. “Immanuel Kant über das moralische Gefühl der Achtung.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 61 (2007): 337–60.Google Scholar
Gram, Moltke S., ed. Interpreting Kant. Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Gregor, Mary J.Critique of Practical Reason: Introduction.” In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Gregor, Mary J., 135–36. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Gregor, Mary J. Laws of Freedom. Oxford: Blackwell, 1963.Google Scholar
Gregoric, Pavel. Aristotle on the Common Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine. “Feeling, Desire, and Interest in Kant’s Theory of Action.” Kant-Studien 92, no. 2 (2001): 153–79.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine. Kant’s Defense of Common Moral Experience: A Phenomenological Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.Google Scholar
Grier, Michelle. Kant’s Doctrine of Transcendental Illusion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Guevara, Daniel. Kant’s Theory of Moral Motivation. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Beauty, Freedom, and Morality: Kant’s Lectures on Anthropology and the Development of his Aesthetic Theory.” In Essays on Kant’s Anthropology, edited by Jacobs, Brian and Kain, Patrick, 135–63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Editorial Notes.” In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: The Critique of the Power of Judgment, edited by Guyer, Paul, 351–97. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Kant. New York: Routledge, 2006.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Claims of Taste. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Experience of Freedom: Essays on Aesthetics and Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Kant’s Distinction between the Sublime and the Beautiful.” Review of Metaphysics 35, no. 4 (1982): 753–83.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Kant’s System of Nature and Freedom: Selected Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Moral Anthropology in Kant’s Aesthetics and Ethics: A Reply to Ameriks and Sherman.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55, no. 2 (1995): 379–91.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Moral Feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide, edited by Denis, Lara, 130–51. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Nature, Art, and Autonomy.” In Kant and the Experience of Freedom: Essays on Aesthetics and Morality, 229–74. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Notes.” In The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: Notes and Fragments, edited by Guyer, Paul, 545625. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “One Act or Two? Hannah Ginsborg on Aesthetic Judgment.” British Journal of Aesthetics (forthcoming).Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Pleasure and Society in Kant’s Theory of Taste.” In Essays in Kant’s Aesthetics, edited by Cohen, Ted and Guyer, Paul, 2154. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. “Reason and Reflective Judgment: Kant on the Significance of Systematicity.” Noûs 24, no. 1 (1990): 1743.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. ed. The Cambridge Companion to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. ed. The Cambridge Companion to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanauer, Tom. “Sublimity and the Ends of Reason: Questions for Deligiorgi.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 74, no. 2 (2016): 195–99.Google Scholar
Hay, Carol. Kantianism, Liberalism, and Feminism: Resisting Oppression. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Edited by Wood, Allen W.. Translated by Nisbet, H. B.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas E. Jr.Servility and Self-Respect.” The Monist 57, no. 1 (January 1973): 87104.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. 1651. Edited by Tuck, Richard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Home, Henry (Lord Kames). Elements of Criticism. 6th ed. Edited by Jones, Peter. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2005.Google Scholar
Horstmann, R.-P.Why Must There Be a Transcendental Deduction in Kant’s Critique of Judgment?” In Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, edited by Förster, Eckart, 157–76. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Fate, David and Norton, Mary J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Selby-Bigge, L. A.. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. Virtue, Vice, and Value. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Hutcheson, Francis. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. 1725. Edited by Leidhold, Wolfgang. Rev. ed. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2008.Google Scholar
Irwin, Terence. The Development of Ethics. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Jacobs, Brian, and Kain, Patrick, eds. Essays on Kant’s Anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Johnson, Robert N.Duties to and Regarding Others.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide, edited by Denis, Lara, 192209. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Jost, Lawrence, and Wuerth, Julian, eds. Perfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.Google Scholar
Katz, Leonard D. “Pleasure.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, June 17, 2016. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pleasure.Google Scholar
Kemp Smith, Norman. A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.Google Scholar
Kirwan, James. The Aesthetic in Kant: A Critique. London: Continuum, 2004.Google Scholar
Kleingeld, Pauline. “The Conative Character of Reason in Kant’s Philosophy.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 36, no. 1 (1998): 7797.Google Scholar
Klimchuk, Dennis. “Three Accounts of Respect for Persons in Kant’s Ethics.” Kantian Review 8, no. 1 (March 2004): 3861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. “Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals.” In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, edited by Peterson, Grethe B.. Vols. 25/26. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 2004.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Kühn, Manfred. Kant: Eine Biographie. München: C. H. Beck, 2003.Google Scholar
Kumar, Apaar. “Kant’s Definition of Sensation.” Kant Studies Online, 2014. www.kantstudiesonline.net.Google Scholar
Kundera, Milan. The Unbearable Lightness of Being. Translated by Heim, Michael Henry. New York: Harper and Row, 1984.Google Scholar
Lipscomb, Benjamin, and Krueger, James. Kant’s Moral Metaphysics: God, Freedom, and Immortality. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2010.Google Scholar
Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Nidditch, Peter H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert B. Kant’s Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyotard, Jean-François. L’Enthousiasme: La critique kantienne de l’ histoire. Paris: Editions Galilée, 1986.Google Scholar
Lyotard, Jean-François. Enthusiasm: The Kantian Critique of History. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009.Google Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf A. Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990.Google Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf A. Orientation and Judgment in Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Massimi, Michela, and Breitenbach, Angela, eds. Kant and the Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming.Google Scholar
McCarty, Richard. “Kantian Moral Motivation and the Feeling of Respect.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 31, no. 3 (1993): 421–35.Google Scholar
McCarty, Richard. Kant’s Theory of Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.Google Scholar
Menzel, Randolph, and Fischer, Julia, eds. Animal Thinking: Contemporary Issues in Comparative Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Merritt, Anna C., Effron, Daniel A., and Monin, Benoît. “Moral-Self-Licensing: When Being Good Frees Us to Be Bad.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 4, no. 5 (May 2010): 344–57.Google Scholar
Merritt, Melissa McBay. “The Moral Source of the Kantian Sublime.” In The Sublime: From Antiquity to the Present, edited by Costelloe, Timothy M., 3749. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.Google Scholar
Merritt, Melissa McBay. “Review of Robert R. Clewis, The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18, no. 3 (2010): 529–32.Google Scholar
Michalson, Gordon, ed. Kant’s Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Morrisson, Iain P. D. Kant and the Role of Pleasure in Moral Action. Athens: Ohio University Press, 2008.Google Scholar
Mudd, Sasha. “Rethinking the Priority of Practical Reason in Kant.” European Journal of Philosophy 24, no. 1 (2016): 78102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?Philosophical Review 83, no. 4 (1974): 435–50. Reprinted in Thomas Nagel. Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morality. Translated by Clark, Maudemarie and Swensen, Alan. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1998.Google Scholar
Osborne, Nicolas. Opinion, croyance, savoir: Recherches sure la pragmatique kantienne de la pensée. PhD diss., University of Lille, 2016.Google Scholar
Park, Kap Hyun. Kant über das Erhabene: Rekonstruktion und Weiterführung der kritischen Theorie des Erhabenen Kants. Würzburg: Königshausen and Neumann, 2009.Google Scholar
Paton, H. J. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. London: Hutchinson and Co., 1947.Google Scholar
Plato, . “Theaetetus.” In Plato: Complete Works, edited by Cooper, John M., 157234. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1997.Google Scholar
Rauscher, Frederick. “The Appendix to the Dialectic and the Canon of Pure Reason: The Positive Role of Reason.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, edited by Guyer, Paul, 290309. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Rayman, Joshua. Kant on Sublimity and Morality. Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 2012.Google Scholar
Reath, Andrews. “Kant’s Theory of Moral Sensibility: Respect for the Moral Law and the Influence of Inclination.” Kant-Studien 80 (1989): 284302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reath, Andrews. “Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 26, no. 4 (1988): 593619.Google Scholar
Reath, Andrews, and Timmermann, Jens, eds. Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Recki, Birgit. “Wie fühlt man sich als vernünftiges Wesen?” In Pathos, Affekt, Gefühl: Die Emotionen in den Künsten, edited by Stumpfhaus, Bernhard and Herding, Klaus, 275–94. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2004.Google Scholar
Reginster, Bernard. “Sympathy in Schopenhauer and Nietzsche.” In Sympathy: A History, edited by Schliesser, Eric, 254–85. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Reimarus, Hermann Samuel. Allgemeine Betrachtungen über die Triebe der Thiere. Bohn: Hamburg, 1760.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas. Kant and the Reach of Reason: Studies in Kant’s Theory of Rational Systematization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Robinson, Jenefer. Deeper than Reason: Emotion and Its Role in Literature, Music, and Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Rohlf, Michael. “The Transition from Nature to Freedom in Kant’s Third Critique.” Kant-Studien 99, no. 3 (2008): 339–60.Google Scholar
Rotenstreich, Nathan. “Morality and Culture: A Note on Kant.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 6, no. 3 (1989): 303–16.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson, 1949.Google Scholar
Sassen, Brigitte. “Common Sense as the Answer to the Paradox of Taste.” In Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des XI Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Vol. 4, 249–59. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2013.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar. “Desires as Demands: How the Second-Person Standpoint Might Be Internal to Reflective Agency.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81, no. 1 (2010): 229–36.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar. “Foregrounding Desire: A Defense of Kant’s Incorporation Thesis.” The Journal of Ethics 15, no. 3 (2011): 1467.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar. “The Nature of Inclination.” Ethics 119, no. 2 (2009): 229–56.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar. “On the Relation between Wanting and Willing.” Philosophical Issues 22, no. 1 (2012): 334–50.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar. “What Are Theories of Desire Theories Of?Analytic Philosophy 55, no. 2 (2014): 131–50.Google Scholar
Schiller, Friedrich. On the Aesthetic Education of Man. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications, 2004.Google Scholar
Schliesser, Eric, ed. Sympathy: A History. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schott, Robin May. Cognition and Eros: A Critique of the Kantian Paradigm. Boston: Beacon Press, 1988.Google Scholar
Sensen, Oliver. Kant on Human Dignity. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2011.Google Scholar
Sensen, Oliver. ed. Kant on Moral Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.Google Scholar
Shell, Susan Meld. “Kant’s ‘True Economy of Human Nature’: Rousseau, Count Verri, and the Problem of Happiness.” In Essays on Kant’s Anthropology, edited by Jacobs, Brian and Kain, Patrick, 174229. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.Google Scholar
Shell, Susan Meld, and Velkley, Richard. Kant’s Observations and Remarks: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherman, Nancy. Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherman, Nancy. “Reasons and Feelings in Kantian Morality.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55, no. 2 (1995): 369–77.Google Scholar
Singleton, Jane. “Kant’s Account of Respect: A Bridge between Rationality and Anthropology.” Kantian Review 12, no. 1 (March 2007): 4060.Google Scholar
Sizer, Laura. “What Feelings Can’t Do.” Mind and Language 21, no. 1 (2006): 108–35.Google Scholar
Sommerlatte, Curtis. “Empirical Cognition in the Transcendental Deduction: Kant’s Starting Point and His Humean Problem.” Kantian Review 21, no. 3 (November 2016): 437–63.Google Scholar
Sorensen, Kelly D.Kant’s Taxonomy of the Emotions.” Kantian Review 6, no. 1 (2002): 109–28.Google Scholar
Stark, Cynthia A.The Rationality of Valuing Oneself: A Critique of Kant on Self-Respect.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 35, no. 1 (January 1997): 6582.Google Scholar
Stratton-Lake, Philip. Kant, Duty, and Moral Worth. London: Routledge, 2000.Google Scholar
Stumpfhaus, Bernhard, and Herding, Klaus, eds. Pathos, Affekt, Gefühl: Die Emotionen in den Künsten. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2004.Google Scholar
Sturm, Thomas. Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen, Münster: Mentis Verlag, 2009.Google Scholar
Sulzer, Johann Georg. Vermischte Philosophische Schriften. Vol. 1. Leipzig: Wiedmanns Erben und Reich, 1773.Google Scholar
Swanton, Christine. “Kant’s Impartial Virtues of Love.” In Perfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics, edited by Jost, Lawrence and Wuerth, Julian, 241–60. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.Google Scholar
Tarbet, David W.The Fabric of Metaphor in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 6, no. 3 (1968): 257–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timmermann, Jens. “Autonomy and Moral Regard for Ends.” In Kant on Moral Autonomy, edited by Sensen, Oliver, 212–24. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.Google Scholar
Velkley, Richard. Being After Rousseau: Philosophy and Culture in Question. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2002.Google Scholar
Verri, Pietro. Del piacere e del dolore ed altri scritt. Milan: Feltrinelli, 1964.Google Scholar
Vico, Giambattista. Selected Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Von Tevenar, Gudren, ed. Nietzsche and Ethics. Oxford: Peter Lang, 2007.Google Scholar
Von Tevenar, Gudren, “Nietzsche’s Objections to Pity and Compassion.” In Nietzsche and Ethics, edited by von Tevenar, Gudrun, 263–82. Oxford: Peter Lang, 2007.Google Scholar
Waibel, Violetta L., and Ruffing, Margit, eds. Proceedings of the 12th International Kant Congress. Berlin: de Gruyter, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Ware, Owen. “The Duty of Self-Knowledge.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79, no. 3 (2009): 671–98.Google Scholar
Wartenberg, Thomas E.Reason and the Practice of Science.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant, edited by Guyer, Paul, 228–48. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Willaschek, Marcus. “The Primacy of Practical Reason and the Idea of a Practical Postulate.” In Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide, edited by Reath, Andrews and Timmermann, Jens, 168–96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.Google Scholar
Williamson, Diane. Kant’s Theory of Emotion: Emotional Universalism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. Psychologia Empirica. 2nd ed. Frankfurt and Leipzig: Renger, 1738.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W.The Antinomies of Pure Reason.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, edited by Guyer, Paul, 245–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W.The Evil in Human Nature.” In Kant’s Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: A Critical Guide, edited by Michalson, Gordon, 3157. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. Fichte’s Ethical Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W.The Final Form of Kant’s Practical Philosophy.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (1997): 120.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. Formulas of the Moral Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. The Free Development of Each: Studies on Freedom, Right, and Ethics in Classical German Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. Kantian Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W.Kant’s History of Ethics.” In Kant’s Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide, edited by Denis, Lara and Sensen, Oliver, 120–37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen W. Kant’s Moral Religion. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1970.Google Scholar
Wuerth, Julian. Kant on Mind, Action, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.Google Scholar
Yovel, Yirmiyahu. Kant and the Philosophy of History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Zammito, John H. The Genesis of Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1992.Google Scholar
Zinkin, Melissa. “Kant and the Pleasure of ‘Mere Reflection.’Inquiry 55, no. 5 (2012): 433–53.Google Scholar
Zinkin, Melissa. “Respect for the Law and the Use of Dynamical Terms in Kant’s Theory of Moral Motivation.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88, no. 1 (2006): 3153.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel. Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of the Critique of Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel. “Kant’s Account of Practical Fanaticism.” In Kant’s Moral Metaphysics: God, Freedom, and Immortality, ed. Lipscomb, Benjamin and Krueger, James, 291317. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2010.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Rachel. “A New Look at Kant’s Theory of Pleasure.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60, no. 3 (2002): 239–52.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Kelly Sorensen, Ursinus College, Pennsylvania, Diane Williamson, Syracuse University, New York
  • Book: Kant and the Faculty of Feeling
  • Online publication: 01 March 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316823453.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Kelly Sorensen, Ursinus College, Pennsylvania, Diane Williamson, Syracuse University, New York
  • Book: Kant and the Faculty of Feeling
  • Online publication: 01 March 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316823453.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Kelly Sorensen, Ursinus College, Pennsylvania, Diane Williamson, Syracuse University, New York
  • Book: Kant and the Faculty of Feeling
  • Online publication: 01 March 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316823453.015
Available formats
×