Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-cnmwb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T22:18:13.688Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2015

Christopher J. Finlay
Affiliation:
University of Birmingham
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Terrorism and the Right to Resist
A Theory of Just Revolutionary War
, pp. 318 - 335
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Al-Azm, Sadik J. 2014. ‘Syria in Revolt: Understanding the Unthinkable War’, Boston Review, 18 August.Google Scholar
Altman, Andrew, and Wellman, Christopher Heath. 2009. A Liberal Theory of International Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Altman, Andrew. 2011. ‘Discrimination’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2011 edition, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/discrimination/.Google Scholar
Amnesty International. 2011. The Battle for Libya: Killings, Disappearances and Torture, London: Amnesty International.Google Scholar
Arafat, Yasser. 1974. Speech to the UN, reprinted in Laqueur, Walter and Rubin, Barry (eds), 2001, The Israel-Arab Reader: A Documentary History of the Middle-East Conflict, sixth edition, New York: Penguin, pp. 177–80.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1958. ‘Epilogue’, to The Origins of Totalitarianism, second edition, Cleveland: World Publishing Co., Meridian Books.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1969. On Violence, New York: Harcourt Brace.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1972. ‘Thoughts on Politics and Revolution’ in Arendt, , Crises of the Republic, New York: Harcourt Brace.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1977. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, revised edition, New York: Penguin Books USA.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 2003. ‘Collective Responsibility’, in Arendt, , Responsibility and Judgement, ed. Kohn, Jerome, New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 2006. On Revolution, New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Auer, Stefan. 2004. Liberal Nationalism in Central Europe, London: Routledge Curzon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baader, Andreas. 2009. ‘On the Geneva Convention’, in Smith, J. and Moncourt, André, The Red Army Faction: A Documentary History, Volume 1: Projectiles for the People, Oakland CA: PM Press.Google Scholar
BBC. 2011. ‘Yemen President Ali Abdullah Saleh Defiant over Exit’, BBC News Middle East, 24 April, www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-middle-east-13181324.Google Scholar
Begby, Endre, Reichberg, Gregory M. and Syse, Henrik. 2010. ‘The Ethics of War. Part II: Contemporary Authors and Issues’, Philosophy Compass, 7(5): 328–47.Google Scholar
Begin, Menachem. 1951. The Revolt, trans. Katz, Samuel and edited with notes by Greenberg, Ivan M., London: W. H. Allen.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles 2004. ‘Human Rights and the Law of Peoples’, in Chatterjee, Deen K. (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bellaigue, Christopher. 2013. ‘The Resurgence of the Kurds’, New York Review of Books, 6 June: 33–5.Google Scholar
Benbaji, Yitzhak. 2009. ‘The War Convention and the Moral Division of Labour’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 593617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benbaji, Yitzhak. 2012. ‘Justice in Asymmetric Wars: A Contractarian Analysis’, Law and Ethics of Human Rights, 6(2): 172200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernstein, Richard J. 2013. Violence: Thinking Without Bannisters, Cambridge: Policy.Google Scholar
Bhatia, Michael V. 2005. ‘Fighting Words: Naming Terrorists, Bandits, Rebels and Other Violence Actors’, Third World Quarterly, 26(1): 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biggar, Nigel. 2013. ‘Christian Just War Reasoning and Two Cases of Rebellion: Ireland 1916–21 and Syria 2011’, Ethics and International Affairs, 27(4): 393400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bin Laden, Osama. 2002. ‘Letter to America’, The Observer, 24 November.Google Scholar
Black, Ian. 2012. ‘Why Bashar al-Assad Stresses al-Qaeda Narrative’, The Guardian, 18 May, www.guardian.co.uk/world/2012/may/18/why-bashar-al-assad-needs-terrorism.Google Scholar
Bloom, Mia. 2011. Bombshell: The Many Faces of Women Terrorists, London: C. Hurst & Co.Google Scholar
Boot, Max. 2013a. Invisible Armies: An Epic History of Guerrilla Warfare from Ancient Times to the Present, New York: Liveright Books.Google Scholar
Boot, Max. 2013b. ‘The Evolution of Irregular War: Insurgents and Guerrillas from Akkadia to Afghanistan’, Foreign Affairs, 1 April.Google Scholar
Boxill, Bernard R., Harvey, Jean, Hill Jr., Thomas E., and Buss, Sarah. 2010. Symposium on ‘The Responsibility to Resist Oppression’, The Journal of Social Philosophy, 41(1): 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandt, R. B. 1972. ‘Utilitarianism and the Rules of War’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(2): 145–65.Google Scholar
Brincat, Shannon. 2009. ‘“Death to Tyrants”: Self-Defence, Human Rights, and Tyrannicide, Part II’, Journal of International Political Theory, 5(1): 7593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen E. 2002. ‘Political Legitimacy and Democracy’, Ethics, 112(4): 689719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen E. 2004. Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen E. 2013a. ‘Secession’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, revised, summer 2013 edition, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/secession/.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen E. 2013b. ‘The Ethics of Revolution and Its Implication for the Ethics of Intervention’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 41(4): 291323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bufacchi, Vittorio. 2007. Violence and Social Justice, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bufacchi, Vittorio. 2012. ‘Making Sense of Social Injustice’ in Bufacchi, Vittorio, Social Injustice: Essays in Political Philosophy, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cabrera, Luis. 2010. The Practice of Global Citizenship, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, Simon. 2005. Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassesse, Antonio. 1984. ‘The Geneva Protocols of 1977 on the Humanitarian Law of Armed Conflict and Customary International Law’, Pacific Basin Law Journal, 3(35): 5118.Google Scholar
Chenowith, Erica and Stephan, Maria. 2011. Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Chiu, Yvonne. 2010. ‘Uniform Exceptions and Rights Violations’, Social Theory and Practice, 36(1): 4477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clausewitz, Carl von. 1993. On War, ed. Howard, Michael, Paret, Peter and Brodie, Bernard, New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 2002. ‘Terrorism, Just War and Supreme Emergency’, in Coady, C. A. J. and O'Keefe, Michael (eds), Terrorism and Justice, Melbourne: Melbourne University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 2004a. ‘Terrorism, Morality and Supreme Emergency’, Ethics, 114(4): 772–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 2004b. ‘Terrorism and Innocence’, Journal of Ethics, 8: 3758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 2008a. Morality and Political Violence, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 2008b. ‘The Status of Combatants’, in Rodin, D. and Shue, H. (eds), Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coates, A. J. 1997. The Ethics of War, Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Corlett, J. Angelo. 2003. Terrorism: A Philosophical Analysis, Dortrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crenshaw, Martha. 1978. Revolutionary Terrorism: The FLN in Algeria, 1954–1962. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.Google Scholar
Crenshaw, Martha. 1981. ‘The Causes of Terrorism’, Comparative Politics, 13(4): 379–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cudd, Ann E. 2006. Analyzing Oppression, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullen, Anthony. 2010. The Concept of Non-International Armed Conflict in International Humanitarian Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Mesquita, Ethan Bueno and Dickson, Eric S. 2007. ‘The Propaganda of the Deed: Terrorism, Counterterrorism, and Mobilization’, American Journal of Political Science, 51(2): 364–81.Google Scholar
de Mesquita, , , Ethan Bueno. 2010. ‘Regime Change and Revolutionary Entrepreneurs’, American Political Science Review, 104(3): 446–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dinstein, Yoram. 2004. The Conduct of Hostilities under the Law of International Armed Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobos, Ned. 2012. Insurrection and Intervention: The Two Faces of Sovereignty, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Donnelly, Jack. 2003. Universal Rights in Theory and Practice, second edition, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Drif Bitat, Zohra. 2012. ‘Our War for Freedom: An Interview with Zohra Drif Bitat’, sixtieth anniversary edition of Gillo Pontecorvo's film, The Battle of Algiers, copyright, Open University.Google Scholar
The Economist. 2014. ‘Russia and Ukraine: The Home Front’: ‘If, on the other hand, Mr Putin moves deeper into Ukraine, the country may descend into a bloody partisan war’. The Economist, 15 March.Google Scholar
El Warfally, Mahmoud Gebril. 2011. ‘What the Libyan Resistance Needs’, New York Times, 12 May, www.nytimes.com/2011/05/13/opinion/13elwarfally.html.Google Scholar
English, Richard. 2004. Armed Struggle: The History of the IRA, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2007. ‘On Following Orders in an Unjust War’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 15: 213–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Martin. 2012. Algeria: France's Undeclared War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2008. ‘Cosmopolitanism, Just War Theory and Legitimate Authority’, International Affairs, 84(5): 963–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2009. ‘Guns, Food, and Liability to Attack in War’, Ethics, 120(1): 3663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2012. Cosmopolitan War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2014. ‘Cosmopolitanism and Wars of Self-Defence’, in Fabre, Cécile and Lazar, Seth (eds), The Morality of Defensive War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile and Lazar, Seth (eds). 2014. The Morality of Defensive War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fallada, Hans. 2009. Alone in Berlin, trans. Hofmann, Michael, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Fanon, Frantz. 1980. The Wretched of the Earth, trans. Farrington, Constance, Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1968. ‘Collective Responsibility’, Journal of Philosophy, 65(21): 674–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1978. ‘Voluntary Euthanasia and the Inalienable Right to Life’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 7(2): 93123.Google ScholarPubMed
Finkelstein, Daniel. 2010. ‘Non-violence Is Heroic, but Not Always Enough’, The Times, Wednesday, 17 November, p. 29.Google Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2006. ‘Violence and Revolutionary Subjectivity, Marx to Žižek’, European Journal of Political Theory, 5(4): 373–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2007. ‘Reform Intervention and Democratic Revolution’, European Journal of International Relations, 13(4): 555–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2008. ‘Self-Defence and the Right to Resist’, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16(1): 85100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2009a. ‘Hannah Arendt's Critique of Violence’, Thesis Eleven, 97: 2645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2009b. ‘How To Do Things with the Word “Terrorist”’, Review of International Studies, 35(4): 751–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2010. ‘Legitimacy and Non-State Political Violence’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(3): 287312.Google Scholar
Finlay, Christopher J. 2013. ‘Fairness and Liability in the Just War: Combatants, Non-Combatants and Lawful Irregulars’, Political Studies, 61: 142–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisk, Robert. 2011. ‘The People vs the President: Syria in Turmoil as Resistance Turns to Insurrection’, The Independent, Wednesday, 8 June, pp. 1–2.Google Scholar
Fletcher, George. 2002. Romantics at War: Glory and Guilt in the Age of Terrorism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Flikschuh, Katrin. 2008. ‘Reason, Right and Revolution: Kant and Locke’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 36(4): 375404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, Franklin L. 1985. Political Murder: From Tyrannicide to Terrorism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2010. ‘The Justification of Human Rights and the Right to Justification: A Reflexive Approach’, Ethics, 120(4): 711–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2014. Justification and Critique: Towards a Critical Theory of Politics, Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Frazer, Elizabeth and Hutchings, Kimberly. 2008. ‘On Politics and Violence: Arendt Contra Fanon’, Contemporary Political Theory, 7: 90108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freedman, Lawrence. 2013. Strategy: A History, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Freire, Paolo. 1996. Pedagogy of the Oppressed, revised edition, trans. Ramos, Myra Bergman, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Friedman, Thomas L. 2014. ‘President Obama Talks to Thomas L. Friedman about Iraq, Putin and Israel’, New York Times, 8 August, www.nytimes.com/2014/08/09/opinion/president-obama-thomas-l-friedman-iraq-and-world-affairs.html?_r=0.Google Scholar
Galtung, Johann. 1969. ‘Violence, Peace and Peace Research’, Journal of Peace Research, 6(3): 167–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, John and Tanguay Renaud, François. 2011. ‘Desert and Avoidability in Self-Defense’, Ethics, 122(1): 111–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garton Ash, Timothy. 2009. ‘Velvet Revolution: The Prospects’, New York Review of Books, 3 December.Google Scholar
Garton Ash, Timothy. 2014. ‘At Stake in Ukraine's Drama is the Future of Putin, Russia and Europe’, The Guardian, 21 February, www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/feb/21/ukraine-putin-russia-europe-independence-disintegration.Google Scholar
Garton Ash, Timothy and Snyder, Timothy. 2005. ‘The Orange Revolution’, New York Review of Books, 28 April.Google Scholar
Gatehouse, Gabriel. 2015. ‘The Untold Story of the Maidan Massacre’, www.bbc.co.uk/news/magazine-31359021.Google Scholar
Geras, Norman. 1989. ‘Our Morals: The Ethics of Revolution’, Socialist Register, 25: 185211.Google Scholar
Gerwarth, Robert. 2012. Hitler's Hangman: The Life of Heydrich, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Gilabert, Pablo. 2011. ‘Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights’, Political Theory, 39(4): 439–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert E. 2003. Reflective Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert E. 2006. What's Wrong with Terrorism? Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Goodin, Robert E. and Lepora, Chiara 2013. Complicity and Compromise, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goodwin, Jeff. 2001. No Other Way Out: States and Revolutionary Movements, 1945–1991, New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodwin, Jeff. 2006. ‘A Theory of Categorical Terrorism’, Social Forces, 84(4): 2027–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, John. 2011. ‘Perpetual Warfare’, The New Statesman, 5 September, pp. 24–9.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie C. 2008. The Contemporary Law of Armed Conflict, third edition, Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Greene, Graham. 1977. ‘The Third Man’, in The Third Man and the Fallen Idol, Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, Arthur. 2003. The Resurrection of Hungary: A Parallel for Ireland, ed. Murray, Patrick, Cork: Cork University Press.Google Scholar
Gross, Michael L. 2003. ‘Fighting by Other Means in the Mideast: A Critical Analysis of Israel's Assassination Policy’, Political Studies, 51: 350–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gross, Michael L. 2010. Moral Dilemmas of Modern War: Torture, Assassination, and Blackmail in an Age of Asymmetric Conflict, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gross, Michael L. 2015. The Ethics of Insurgency: A Critical Guide to Just Guerrilla Warfare. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grotius, Hugo. 2005. Rights of War and Peace, ed. Tuck, Richard, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
The Guardian. 2011a. ‘Bahrain in Crisis and Middle East Protests, Live Blog’, www.guardian.co.uk/world/blog/2011/feb/17/bahrain-crisis-middle-east-protests-live-blog.Google Scholar
The Guardian. 2011b. ‘Violence in Bahrain and Libya – Friday 18 February’, www.guardian.co.uk/world/blog/2011/feb/18/middle-east-protests-live-updates.Google Scholar
Guevara, Che. 1969. Guerrilla Warfare (Pelican Latin American Library), Harmondsworth: Pelican Books.Google Scholar
Harkabi, Yesosefat. 2001. ‘Al-Fatah's Doctrine’, in Laqueur, Walter and Rubin, Barry (eds), The Israel-Arab Reader: A Documentary History of the Middle-East Conflict, sixth edition, New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Harris, John. 1980. Violence and Responsibility, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hass, Amira. 2003. ‘Who in Israel Knows or Cares?’ Haaretz, 18 June.Google Scholar
Havel, Václav. 1991. ‘The Power of the Powerless’, in Havel, , Open Letters: Selected Prose, London: Faber & Faber.Google Scholar
Hay, Carol. 2011. ‘The Obligation to Resist Oppression’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 41(1): 2145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, Virginia. 2008a. ‘Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals’, in Held, , How Terrorism Is Wrong: Morality and Political Violence, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, Virginia. 2008b. How Terrorism Is Wrong, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyd, David. 2012. ‘Supererogation’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, winter 2012 edition, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/supererogation/.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1996. Leviathan, ed. Tuck, Richard, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Bruce. 2006. Inside Terrorism, revised edition, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Honderich, Ted. 2003. Terrorism for Humanity: Inquiries in Political Philosophy, London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Honoré, Tony. 1988. ‘The Right to Rebel’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 8(1): 3454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, William. 2009. Carl Schmitt's International Thought: Order and Orientation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horne, Alistair. 2002. A Savage War of Peace: Algeria 1954–1962, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Human Rights Watch. 2009. ‘Rockets from Gaza’, 6 August, www.hrw.org/en/node/84867/section/5#_ftnref24.Google Scholar
Human Rights Watch. 2011. ‘Libya: Security Forces Kill 84 over Three Days’, www.hrw.org/en/news/2011/02/18/libya-security-forces-kill-84-over-three-days.Google Scholar
Human Rights Watch. 2014. ‘“Until the Very End”: Politically Motivated Imprisonment in Uzbekistan’, www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/uzbekistan0914_ForUpload.pdf.Google Scholar
Hume, David 1902. Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, second edition, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 2011. A Treatise of Human Nature: Volume 1: Texts, eds Norton, David Fate and Norton, Mary J., Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2005. ‘Proportionality in the Morality of War’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33(1): 3466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2007. ‘Liability and Just Cause’, Ethics and International Affairs, 20(2): 199218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2008. ‘Proportionality and Necessity’, in May, Larry (ed.), War: Essays on Political Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ignatieff, Michael. 2002. ‘Human Rights, the Laws of War, and Terrorism’, Social Research, 69(4): 1137–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ignatieff, Michael. 2004. The Lesser Evil: Political Ethics in an Age of Terror, Toronto: Penguin Canada.Google Scholar
Iser, Mattias. Forthcoming. A Theory of Legitimate Violence.Google Scholar
Johnson, James Turner. 1999. Morality and Contemporary Warfare, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, James Turner. 2002. ‘Paul Ramsey and the Recovery of the Just War Idea’, Journal of Military Ethics, I: 136–44.Google Scholar
Johnson, James Turner. 2013. ‘Ad Fontes: The Question of Rebellion and Moral Tradition on the Use of Force’, Ethics and International Affairs, 27(4): 371–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judt, Tony. 2010. Postwar: A History of Europe Since 1945, London: Vintage.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. M. 2011. Ethics for Enemies: Terror, Torture, and War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 2006. ‘An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?’ in Kleingeld, Pauline (ed.), Colclasure, David L. (trans.) Toward Perpetual Peace and other Writings on Politics, Peace, and History, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis and Schulte, Erich. 2002. ‘The Rhetoric of “Terrorism” and its Consequences’, Journal of Political and Military Sociology, 30(1): 172–96.Google Scholar
Kelsay, John. 2013. ‘Muslim Discourse on Rebellion’, Ethics and International Affairs, 27(4): 379–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kershaw, Ian. 2009. Hitler, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Kershner, Isabel. 2011. ‘Palestinians Say U.N. Gamble Is Worth the Risk’, New York Times, 15 September.Google Scholar
Kinsella, Helen M. 2005. ‘Discourses of Difference: Civilians, Combatants and Compliance with the Laws of War’, Review of International Studies, 31: 163–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinsella, Helen M. 2006. ‘Gendering Grotius: Sex and Sex Difference in the Laws of War’, Political Theory, 34: 161–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinsella, Helen M. 2011. The Image Before the Weapon: A Critical History of the Distinction between Combatant and Civilian, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuperman, Alan J. 2005. ‘Suicidal Rebellions and the Moral Hazard of Humanitarian Intervention’, Ethnopolitics, 4(2): 149–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuperman, Alan J. 2008. ‘The Moral Hazard of Humanitarian Intervention: Lessons from the Balkans’, International Studies Quarterly, 52: 4980CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuperman, Alan J. 2013. ‘Model Humanitarian Intervention? Reassessing NATO's Libya Campaign’, International Security, 38(1): 105–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kutz, Christopher. 2000. Complicity: Ethics and Law for a Collective Age, New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kutz, Christopher. 2005. ‘The Difference Uniforms Make: Collective Violence in Criminal Law and War’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33(2): 148–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Douglas. 1988. The Ethics of War and Peace, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Law, Randall. 2009. Terrorism: A History, Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2010. ‘The Responsibility Dilemma for Killing in War: A Review Essay’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38(2): 180213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2014a. ‘Necessity and Non-Combatant Immunity’, Review of International Studies, 40(1): 5376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, Seth. 2014b. ‘National Defence, Self-Defence, and the Problem of Political Aggression’, in Fabre, Cécile and Lazar, Seth (eds), The Morality of Defensive War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levi, Primo. 2000. If Not Now, When? trans. Weaver, William, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. 2006a. ‘Racial Profiling versus Community’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23(2): 191205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. 2006b. ‘The Badness of Discrimination’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9: 167–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John 1988. Two Treatises of Government, ed. Laslett, P., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovett, Frank. 2010. A General Theory of Domination and Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luban, David. 1980. ‘Just War and Human Rights’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9(2): 160–81.Google Scholar
Mandela, Nelson. 2002. No Easy Walk to Freedom, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Manna, Haytham. 2012. ‘Syria's Opposition Has Been Led Astray by Violence’, The Guardian, Friday, 22 June, www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2012/jun/22/syria-opposition-led-astray-by-violence.Google Scholar
Mapel, David R. 2010. ‘Moral Liability to Killing and Symmetrical Self-Defence’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(2): 198217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marighela, Carlos. 1971. For the Liberation of Brazil, trans. Butt, John and Sheed, Rosemary, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Massing, M. 2008. ‘The Volunteer Army: Who Fights and Why?’ New York Review of Books, 55(5): 34–6.Google Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1975. ‘Conventions and the Morality of War’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4: 117–31.Google Scholar
May, Larry. 2008. Aggression and Crimes against Peace, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAdam, Doug. 2009. ‘The US Civil Rights Movement: Power from Below and Above, 1945–70’, in Garton Ash, Timothy and Roberts, Adam (eds), Civil Resistance and Power Politics: The Experience of Nonviolent Action from Gandhi to the Present, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 5874.Google Scholar
McAllister, Ian. 2004. ‘The Armalite and the Ballot Box: Sinn Fein's Electoral Strategy in Northern Ireland’, Electoral Studies, 23: 123–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff and McKim, Robert. 1993. ‘The Just War and the Gulf War’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23(4): 501–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 1994. ‘Innocence, Self-Defence and Killing in War’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 2(3): 193221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2004a. ‘War as Self-Defense’, Ethics and International Affairs, 18(1): 7580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2004b. ‘The Ethics of Killing in War’, Ethics, 114: 693733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2005. ‘Just Cause for War’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19(3): 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2006. ‘On the Moral Equality of Combatants’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 14: 377–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2008. ‘The Morality of War and the Law of War’, in Rodin, D. and Shue, H. (eds), Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2009a. Killing in War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2009b. ‘War, Terrorism, and the War on Terror’, in Miller, Christopher (ed.), ‘War on Terror’: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 2006, Man-chester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2009c. ‘Humanitarian Intervention, Consent, and Proportionality’, in Davis, N. Ann, Keshen, Richard, and McMahan, Jeff (eds), Ethics and Humanity: Themes from the Philosophy of Jonathan Glover, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2010a. ‘The Just Distribution of Harm between Combatants and Noncombatants’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38(4): 342–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2010b. ‘Responsibility, Permissibility and Vicarious Agency’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80: 673–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2011a. ‘Proportionality in the Afghanistan War’, Ethics and International Affairs, 25(2): 143–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2011b. ‘Who Is Morally Liable to be Killed in War’, Analysis Review, 71(3): 544–9.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2012a. ‘Targeted Killing: Murder, Combat, or Law Enforcement?’, in Altman, Andrew, Finkelstein, Claire, and Ohlin, Jens David (eds), Targeted Killings: Law and Morality in an Asymmetrical World, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2012b. ‘Hobbesian Defences of Orthodox Just War Theory’, in Hobbes Today: Insights for the Twenty-First Century, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 304–19.Google Scholar
McPherson, Lionel K. 2004. ‘Innocence and Responsibility in War’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 34(4): 485506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, Lionel K. 2007. ‘Is Terrorism Distinctively Wrong?’ Ethics, 117: 524–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meisels, Tamar. 2008. The Trouble with Terror: Liberty, Security and the Response to Terrorism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1984. ‘A Few Words on Non-intervention’, The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. XXI, Toronto: Toronto University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 1984. ‘The Use and Abuse of Political Violence’, Political Studies, 32: 401–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moloney, , Ed. 2002. A Secret History of the IRA, London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Morkevicius, Valerie. 2013. ‘Why We Need a Just Rebellion Theory’, Ethics and International Affairs, 27(4): 401–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller, Jan-Werner. 2003. A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Müller, Jan-Werner. 2011. Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth-Century Europe, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Nabulsi, Karma. 1999. Traditions of War: Occupation, Resistance, and the Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1972. ‘War and Massacre’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(2): 123–44.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1991. Mortal Questions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Narveson, Jan. 1965. ‘Pacifism: A Philosophical Analysis’, Ethics, 75(4): 259–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narveson, Jan. 2002. ‘Collective Responsibility’, Journal of Ethics, 6: 179–98.Google Scholar
Nathanson, Stephen. 2010. Terrorism and the Ethics of War, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neff, Stephen C. 2005. War and the Law of Nations: A General History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickel, James. 1987. Making Sense of Human Rights: Philosophical Reflections on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Nickel, James. 2007. Making Sense of Human Rights, second edition, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Norman, Richard. 1995. Ethics, Killing and War, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Driscoll, Cian. 2008. Renegotiation of the Just War Tradition and the Right to War in the Twenty-First Century, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ophüls, Marcel. 1969. The Sorrow and the Pity (film).Google Scholar
Orend, Brian. 2000. ‘Michael Walzer on Resorting to Force’, Canadian Journal of Political Science, 33(3): 523–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owens, Patricia. 2007. Between War and Politics: International Relations and the Thought of Hannah Arendt, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parry, Jonathan. 2015. ‘Just War Theory, Legitimate Authority, and Irregular Belligerency’, Philosophia, published online, 6 March (DOI:10.1007/s11406-014-9577-z)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattison, James. 2010. Humanitarian Intervention and the Responsibility to Protect: Who Should Intervene? Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2002. World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms, Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2005. ‘Severe Poverty as a Violation of Negative Duties’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19(1): 5583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pontecorvo, Gillo and Solinas, Franco. 1966. The Battle of Algiers (screenplay by Solinas; directed by Pontecorvo).Google Scholar
Portelli, Alessandro. 2003. The Order Has Been Carried Out: History, Memory, and Meaning of a Nazi Massacre in Rome, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Primoratz, Igor. 1997. ‘The Morality of Terrorism’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 14(3): 221–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Primoratz, Igor. 2002. ‘Michael Walzer's Just War Theory: Some Issues of Responsibility’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 5: 221–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Primoratz, Igor. 2010. ‘Civilian Immunity in War: Its Grounds, Scope and Weight’, in Primoratz, Igor (ed.), Civilian Immunity in War, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2142.Google Scholar
Primoratz, Igor. 2012. Terrorism: A Philosophical Inquiry, Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Quinn, Warren. 1989. ‘Actions, Intentions and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 18(4): 334–51.Google ScholarPubMed
Quong, Jonathan. 2005. ‘Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 4: 301–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rapoport, David C. 2004. ‘The Four Waves of Modern Terrorism’, in Cronin, Audrey Kurth and Ludes, J. (eds), Attacking Terrorism: Elements of a Grand Strategy, Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999a. A Theory of Justice, revised edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999b. Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999c. ‘The Justification of Civil Disobedience’, in Rawls, Samuel Freeman (ed.), Collected Papers, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John. 2007. Lectures on Political Philosophy, ed. Freeman, Samuel, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2010. ‘Human Rights without Foundations’, in The Philosophy of International Law, eds Beeson, Samantha and Tasioulas, John, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reichberg, Gregory M. 2008. ‘Jus ad Bellum’, in May, Larry (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Reitberger, Magnus. 2013. ‘License to Kill: Is Legitimate Authority a Requirement for Just War?’ International Theory, 5(1): 6493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian. 2013. Individual Rights and the Making of the International System, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, Louise. 2006. What Terrorists Want: Understanding the Terrorist Threat, London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Risse, Mathias, and Zeckhauser, Richard. 2004. ‘Racial Profiling’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 32.(2): 131–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Adam. 2008. ‘The Equal Application of the Laws of War’, International Review of the Red Cross, 90: 931–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Adam. 2009. ‘Introduction’, in Roberts, Adam and Garton Ash, Timothy (eds), Civil Resistance and Power Politics: The Experience of Non-Violent Action from Gandhi to the Present, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Adam and Garton Ash, Timothy (eds). 2009. Civil Resistance and Power Politics: The Experience of Nonviolent Action from Gandhi to the Present, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Andrew. 2010. The Storm of War: A New History of the Second World War, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Roberts, G. B. 1985–6. ‘The New Rules for Waging War: The Case Against Ratification of Additional Protocol 1’, Virginia Journal of International Law, 26: 109–70.Google Scholar
Rodin, David and Shue, Henry (eds). 2008. Just and Unjust Warriors, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, David. 2002. War and Self-Defense, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, David. 2004. ‘Terrorism without Intention’, Ethics, 114(4): 752–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, David. 2006. ‘The Ethics of Asymmetric War’, in Sorabji, Richard and Rodin, David (eds), The Ethics of War: Shared Problems in Different Traditions, Farnham: Ashgate, 153–68.Google Scholar
Ryan, Cheyney C. 1983. ‘Self-Defence, Pacifism, and the Possibility of Killing’, Ethics, 93(3): 508–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saul, Ben. 2006. Defining Terrorism in International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2003. ‘Human Rights as a Neutral Concern’, in Scanlon, T. M., The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 2006. ‘Is Terrorism Morally Distinctive?’ Journal of Political Philosophy, 14: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schell, Jonathan. 2005. The Unconquerable World: Power, Nonviolence, and the Will of the People, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 1996. The Concept of the Political, trans. and introduction by Schwab, George, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 2003. The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Just Publicum Europeaum, trans. Ulmen, G. L., New York: Telos Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 2007. Theory of the Partisan: Intermediate Commentary on the Concept of the Political, New York: TelosPress Publishing.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 2011. ‘The Turn to the Discriminating Concept of War’ in Nunan, Timothy (ed.), Writings on War, Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Michael N. 2009. ‘Human Shields and International Humanitarian Law’, Columbia Journal of Transnational Law, 47: 292338.Google Scholar
Schofield, Philip. 2006. Utility and Democracy: The Political Thought of Jeremy Bentham, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwenkenbecher, Anne. 2012. Terrorism: A Philosophical Enquiry, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, Jonathan. 1992. ‘The Law of War: Grotius, Sidney, Locke and the Political Theory of Rebellion’, History of Political Thought, 13(4): 565–85.Google Scholar
Shanahan, Timothy. 2008. The Provisional Irish Republican Army and the Morality of Terrorism, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2005. The State of Democratic Theory, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sharp, Gene. 2010. From Dictatorship to Democracy: A Conceptual Framework for Liberation, fourth US edition, Boston, MA: The Albert Einstein Institution.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith. 1998. ‘The Liberalism of Fear’, in Shklar, Judith, Political Thought and Political Thinkers, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry. 1996. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and US Foreign Policy, second edition, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sidney, Algernon 1996. Discourses Concerning Government, ed. West, Thomas G., revised edition, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Silvermint, Daniel. 2013. ‘Resistance and Well-being’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 21(4): 405–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 1979. Moral Principles and Political Obligations, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 1993. The Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 1999. ‘Justification and Legitimacy’, Ethics, 109: 739–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 2001. ‘The Obligations of Citizens and the Justification of Conscription’, in Simmons, A. J., Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 1998. Liberty before Liberalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 2002. Visions of Politics 1: Regarding Method, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 2008. Hobbes and Republican Liberty, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Slomp, Gabriella. 2005. ‘The Theory of the Partisan: Carl Schmitt's Neglected Legacy’, History of Political Thought, 26(3): 502–19.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard 1973. Utilitarianism, For and Against, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, Saul. 2004. ‘Terrorism, Justification and Illusion’, Ethics, 114(4): 790805.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. and Moncourt, André 2009. The Red Army Faction: A Documentary History, Volume 1: Projectiles for the People, Oakland, CA: PM Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Matthew Noah. 2008a. ‘Terrorism, Shared Rules, and Trust’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(2): 201–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Matthew Noah. 2008b. ‘Rethinking Sovereignty, Rethinking Revolution’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 36: 405–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solis, Gary D. 2010. The Law of Armed Conflict: International Humanitarian Law in War, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorel, Georges. 1999. Reflections on Violence, ed. Jennings, Jeremy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sreedhar, Susanne. 2010. Hobbes on Resistance: Defying the Leviathan, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Statman, Daniel. 2008. ‘On the Success Condition for Legitimate Self-Defence’, Ethics, 118: 659–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinhoff, Uwe. 2007. On the Ethics of War and Terrorism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinhoff, Uwe. 2010. ‘In Defence of Guerrillas’, Diametros, 23: 84103.Google Scholar
Steinhoff, Uwe. 2014. ‘Finlay on Legitimate Authority: a Critical Comment’, (May 5, 2014). Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2445879 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2445879.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stolberg, Sheryl Gay. 2011. ‘Shy U.S. Intellectual Created Playbook Used in a Revolution’, New York Times, 16 February, www.nytimes.com/2011/02/17/world/middleeast/17sharp.html.Google Scholar
Tadros, Victor. 2013. The Ends of Harm: The Moral Foundations of Criminal Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Frederick. 2005. Dresden: 13 February 1945, London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Telegraph. 2006. ‘Hamas's Weasel Words Bode Ill for Peace’, The Daily Telegraph, 17 April www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/telegraph-view/3624400/Hamass-weasel-words-bode-ill-for-peace.html.Google Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1986. ‘Self-Defense and Rights’, in Parent, William (ed.) Rights, Restitution and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Townshend, Charles. 2013. The Republic: The Fight for Irish Independence, London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Trotsky, Leon. 1973. 1905, trans. Bostock, Anya, Harmondsworth: Pelican Books.Google Scholar
Uniacke, Suzanne. 2011. ‘Proportionality and Self-Defence’, Law and Philosophy, 30: 253–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
United Nations. 2011. ‘Report of the Secretary General's Panel of Experts on Accountability in Sri Lanka’, 31 March.Google Scholar
US Catholic Bishops. 1992. ‘The Challenge of Peace: God's Promise and Our Response’, in Elshtain, Jean Bethke (ed.), Just War Theory, New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2012. ‘Human Rights, Freedom, and Political Authority’, Political Theory, 40(5): 573601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verboven, Moenraad, Carlier, Myriam, and Dumolyna, Jan. 2013. Short Manual to the Art of Prosopography, http://prosopography.modhist.ox.ac.uk/images/01%20Verboven%20pdf.pdf.Google Scholar
Viannay, Philippe. 1944. ‘Le Devoir de Tuer’ (signed ‘Indomitus’), Défense de la France, no. 44.Google Scholar
Vitoria, Fancisco de. 1991. ‘The Law of War’, in Pagden, Anthony and Lawrence, Jeremy (eds), Vitoria: Political Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2004. ‘Terrorism and the Uses of Terror’, Journal of Ethics, 8: 535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2010. ‘Civilians, Terrorism, and Deadly Serious Conventions’, in Waldron, J., Torture, Terror and Trade-Offs: Philosophy for the Whitehouse, Oxford: Oxford University Press: 80110.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1970. Obligations: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1973. ‘Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 2(2): 160–80.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations, third edition, 2000, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1980. ‘The Moral Standing of States: A Response to Four Critics’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9(3): 209–29.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 2004. Arguing About War, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 2006. ‘Terrorism and Just War’, Philosophia, 34: 312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Max 1970. ‘Politics as a Vocation’, in From Max Weber: Essays on Sociology, eds Gerth, Hans H. and Mills, C. Wright, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Weizman, Eyal. 2012. The Least of All Possible Evils: Humanitarian Violence from Arendt to Gaza, London: Verso.Google Scholar
Wellman, Carl. 1979. ‘On Terrorism Itself’, Journal of Value Inquiry, 13(4): 250–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wellman, Christopher Heath. 2005. A Theory of Secession, New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 2005. ‘The Nature of Rights’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33: 223–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Werner, Wouter G. 2010. ‘The Changing Face of Enmity: Carl Schmitt's International Theory and the Evolution of the Legal Concept of War’, International Theory, 2(3): 351–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheeler, Nicholas. 2000. Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Whetham, David. 2010. ‘The Just War Tradition: A Pragmatic Compromise’, in Whetham, David (ed.), Ethics, Law and Military Operations, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wilkins, Burleigh T. 1992. Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Windrow, Martin. 2004. The Last Valley: Dien Bien Phu and the French Defeat in Vietnam, Weidenfield & Nicolson.Google Scholar
Winter, Yves. 2011. ‘The Asymmetric War Discourse and Its Moral Economies: A Critique’, International Theory, 3(3): 488514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Žižek, Slavoj. 2012. ‘Introduction’ to Wahnich, Sophie, In Defence of the Terror: Liberty or Death in the French Revolution, London: Verso.Google Scholar
Zohar, Noam. 1993. ‘Collective War and Individualistic Ethics’, Political Theory, 21: 606–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Christopher J. Finlay, University of Birmingham
  • Book: Terrorism and the Right to Resist
  • Online publication: 05 August 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139644341.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Christopher J. Finlay, University of Birmingham
  • Book: Terrorism and the Right to Resist
  • Online publication: 05 August 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139644341.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Christopher J. Finlay, University of Birmingham
  • Book: Terrorism and the Right to Resist
  • Online publication: 05 August 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139644341.013
Available formats
×