Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T04:04:44.299Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 December 2021

Sean Kelsey
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Angioni, L. (2001). Explanation and definition in Physics I 1. Apeiron, 34(4), 307320.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. (1967). Aristote et la langage. Annales de La Faculté de Lettres et Sciences Humaines d’Aix, Études Classiques, 2, 85105. Reprinted in Aubenque 2017, pp. 11–30.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. (1982). Pensée et langage chez Aristote. À propos des catégories. Zeitschrift für Phonetik, Sprachwissenschaft, und Kommunikationsforschung, 614619. Reprinted in Aubenque 2017, pp. 31–38.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. (2017). Problèmes Aristotéliciens, Vol. I. Philosophie Théorique. Paris: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Barker, A. (1977). Music and mathematics: Theophrastus against the number-theorists. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, 23, 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, A. (1981). Aristotle on perception and ratios. Phronesis, 26(3), 248266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, A. (1984). Aristoxenus’ theorems and the foundations of harmonic science. Ancient Philosophy, 4(1), 2364.Google Scholar
Barker, A. (1985). Theophrastus on pitch and melody. In Fortenbaugh, W. W., Huby, P. M., & Long, A. A., eds., Theophrastus of Eresus: On His Life and Work. New Brunswick: Transaction Books, pp. 289324.Google Scholar
Barker, A. (2002). Words for sounds. In Tuplin, C. & Rihll, T. E., eds., Science and Mathematics in Ancient Greek Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2235.Google Scholar
Barker, A. (2007). The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beere, J. B. (2009). Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berti, E. (1978). The intellection of “indivisibles” according to Aristotle, De Anima III 6. In Lloyd, G. E. R. & Owen, G. E. L., eds., Aristotle on the Mind and the Senses. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 141163.Google Scholar
Berti, E. (1994). Encore sur l’intellection des “indivisibles” selon Aristote, De Anima III 6. In Alberti, A. M., ed., Realtà e Ragione. Studi di Filosofia Antica, Florence: Leo S. Olschki, pp. 123136.Google Scholar
Blair, G. A. (1992). Energeia and Entelecheia: “Act” in Aristotle. Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press.Google Scholar
Bolotin, D. (2018). Aristotle. De Anima (On Soul). Mercer: Mercer University Press.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (2005). Perception naturalized in Aristotle’s De Anima. In Salles, R., ed., Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics in Ancient Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 209244.Google Scholar
Bonitz, H. (1870). Index Aristotelicus. Berlin: Reimer.Google Scholar
Bos, A. P. (2010). The soul’s instrument for touching in Aristotle, On the Soul II 11, 422b34–423a21. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 92(1), 89102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowin, J. (2011). Aristotle on various types of alteration in De Anima II 5. Phronesis, 56(2), 138161.Google Scholar
Bowin, J. (2012). De Anima II 5 on the activation of the senses. Ancient Philosophy, 32(1), 87104.Google Scholar
Bredlow, L. A. (2011a). Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Parmenides’ theory of cognition (B 16). Apeiron, 44(3), 219263.Google Scholar
Bredlow, L. A. (2011b). Parmenides and the grammar of being. Classical Philology, 106(4), 283298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broackes, J. (1999). Aristotle, objectivity, and perception. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 17, 57113.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (1993). Aristotle’s perceptual realism. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 31(S1), 137159.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (2016). Corporeal Gods, with reference to Plato and Aristotle. In Buchheim, T., Meissner, D., & Wachsmann, N., eds., Σω̃μα: Körperkonzepte und körperliche Existenz in der antiken Philosophie und Literatur. Hamburg: F. Meiner, pp. 159182.Google Scholar
Bronstein, D. (2016). Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (1982). Idealism and Greek philosophy: what Descartes saw and Berkeley missed. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series, 13, 1950.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1992). Is an Aristotelian philosophy of mind still credible? (a draft). In Nussbaum, M. C. & Rorty, A. O., eds., Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 1526.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1996). Aristote voit du rouge et entend un “do”: combien se passe-t-il de choses? Remarques sur De Anima, II, 7–8. In Romeyer-Dherbey, G. & Viano, C., eds., Corps et Âme: Sur le De Anima d’Aristote. Paris: J. Vrin, pp. 149167.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2001). Aquinas on “spiritual change” in perception. In Perler, D., ed., Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality. Leiden: Brill, pp. 129153.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2002). De Anima II 5. Phronesis, 47(1), 2890.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2008). Aristotle’s Divine Intellect. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Bynum, T. (1987). A new look at Aristotle’s theory of perception. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 4(2), 163178.Google Scholar
Carter, J. W. (2018). Does the soul weave? Reconsidering De Anima 1.4, 408a29b18. Phronesis, 63(1), 2563.Google Scholar
Carter, J. W. (2019). How Aristotle changes Anaxagoras’s mind. Apeiron, 52(1), 128.Google Scholar
Castelli, L. M. (2018). Aristotle. Metaphysics. Book Iota. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (1996). Why Aristotle needs imagination. Phronesis, 41(1), 2055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (1999). Aristotle’s two intellects: a modest proposal. Phronesis, 44(3), 199227.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (2000). Aristotle’s argument for why the understanding is not compounded with the body. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 16, 135175.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (2005). The spirit and the letter: Aristotle on perception. In Salles, R., ed., Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics in Ancient Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 245320.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (n.d.). Aristotle on perceptual content. University of Michigan.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (2000). Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Charlton, W. (1970). Aristotle’s Physics. Books 1 & 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Coates, C., & Lennox, J. (2020). Aristotle on the unity of the nutritive and reproductive functions. Phronesis, 65(4), 414466.Google Scholar
Cohoe, C. (2013). Why the intellect cannot have a bodily organ: De Anima 3.4. Phronesis, 58(4), 347377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohoe, C. (2016). When and why understanding needs phantasmata: a moderate interpretation of Aristotle’s De Memoria and De Anima on the role of images in intellectual activities. Phronesis, 61(3), 337372.Google Scholar
Coope, U. (2011). Time for Aristotle: Physics IV. 10–14. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1999). Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2010). How are episodes of thought initiated according to Aristotle? In Van Riel, G., Destrée, P., Crawford, C. K., & Campe, L. Van, eds., Ancient Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Anima. Leuven: Leuven University Press, pp. 141.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2014). Activity, passivity, and perceptual discrimination in Aristotle, In J. Silva, F. & Yrjönsuuri, M., eds., Active Perception in the History of Philosophy: from Plato to Modern Philosophy. Cham, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 3154.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2017). Aristoteles. Über die Seele. De Anima. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K., & Gregoric, P. (2013). Aristotle’s model of animal motion. Phronesis, 58(1), 5297.Google Scholar
Crager, A. (2018). Three ones and Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Metaphysics, 1(1), 110134.Google Scholar
Crubellier, M. (2020). L’âme comme la main: traduction et commentaire du chapitre III 8. In Guyomarc’h, G., Louguet, C., & Murgier, C., eds., Aristote et l’Âme Humaine: Lectures de De Anima III offertes à Michel Crubellier. Leuven: Peeters, pp. 221253.Google Scholar
Crubellier, M., & Laks, A. (2009). Introduction. In Crubellier, M. & Laks, A., eds., Aristotle’s Metaphysics Beta. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 124.Google Scholar
De Haas, F. (2005). The discriminating capacity of the soul in Aristotle’s theory of learning. In Salles, R., ed., Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics in Ancient Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 321344.Google Scholar
Delcomminette, S. (2018). Aristote et la Nécessité. Paris: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Delcomminette, S. (2020). De Anima III 6. In Guyomarc’h, G., Louguet, C., & Murgier, C., eds., Aristote et l’Âme Humaine: Lectures de De Anima III offertes à Michel Crubellier. Leuven: Peeters, pp. 157184.Google Scholar
Dilcher, R. (2006). Parmenides on the place of mind. In King, R. A. H., ed., Common to Body and Soul: Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behaviour in Greco-Roman Antiquity. New York: de Gruyter, pp. 3148.Google Scholar
Dimock, G. E., & Murray, A. T. (2014). Homer. The Odyssey, revised edn, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Driscoll, J. (1992). The Anaxagorean assumption in Aristotle’s account of mind. In Anton, J. P. & Preus, A., eds., Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy. V: Aristotle’s Ontology. New York: State University of New York Press, pp. 273292.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. (2018). Science unlimited? The challenges of scientism. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved from https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/science-unlimited-the-challenges-of-scientismGoogle Scholar
Ebert, T. (1983). Aristotle on what is done in perceiving. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung, 37(2), 181198.Google Scholar
Falcon, A. (2018). Physics I.1. In Quarantotto, D., ed., Aristotle’s Physics Book I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 4159.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1988). Being and becoming in Plato. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume, 37–52.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1996). La théorie aristotélicienne d’intellect agent. In Romeyer-Dherbey, G. & Viano, C., eds., Corps et Âme: Sur le De Anima d’Aristote. Paris: J. Vrin, pp. 376390.Google Scholar
Frey, C. (2007). Organic unity and the matter of man. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 32, 167204.Google Scholar
Frey, C. (2015). From blood to flesh: homonymy, unity, and ways of being in Aristotle. Ancient Philosophy, 35(2), 375394.Google Scholar
Ganson, T. S. (1997). What’s wrong with the Aristotelian theory of sensible qualities? Phronesis, 42(3), 263282.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. (2009). The theory of the elements in De Caelo 3 and 4. In Bowen, A. C. & Wildberg, C., eds., New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Caelo. Leiden: Brill, pp. 139161.Google Scholar
Gregoric, P. (2007). Aristotle on the Common Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gregoric, P., & Pfeiffer, C. (2015). Grasping Aristotle’s intellect. Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale, 26, 1331.Google Scholar
Guyer, P., & Horstmann, R.-P. (2020). Idealism. In Zalta, E. N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University: Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved from: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/idealismGoogle Scholar
Heinaman, R. (2007). Actuality, potentiality and De Anima II.5. Phronesis, 52(2), 139187.Google Scholar
Herzberg, S. (2016). God as pure thinking. An interpretation of Metaphysics Λ 7, 1072b1416. In Horn, C., ed., Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda – New Essays. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 157180.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. D. (1907). Aristotle. De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hussey, E. (2006). Parmenides on thinking. In King, R. A. H., ed., Common to Body and Soul: Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behaviour in Greco-Roman Antiquity. Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 1330.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. (2002). Imprinted on the mind: passive and active in Aristotle’s theory of perception. In Saunders, B. & Van Bakel, J., eds., Theories, Technologies, Instrumentalities of Color, Lanham, MD: University Press of America, pp. 169188.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (1997). Aristotle on the Sense-Organs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (2012). The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. A. (2012). Aristotle on odour and smell. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 43, 143183.Google Scholar
Johnstone, M. A. (2013). Aristotle on sounds. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21(4), 631648.Google Scholar
Kalderon, M. E. (2015). Form without Matter: Empedocles and Aristotle on Color Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2006). Aristotle Physics I 8. Phronesis, 4(4), 330361.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2008). The place of I 7 in the argument of Physics I. Phronesis, 53(2), 180208.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2010). Hylomorphism in Aristotle’s Physics. Ancient Philosophy, 30(1), 107124.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2015). Empty words. In Ebrey, D., ed., Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 199216.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2018). Color, transparency, and light in Aristotle. Phronesis, 63, 209210.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. (2013). The Activity of Being: An Essay on Aristotle’s Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. (2014). Virtues of Thought: Essays on Plato and Aristotle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kosman, L. A. (1992). What does the maker mind make? In Rorty, A. O. & Nussbaum, M. C., eds., Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 343358.Google Scholar
Laks, A. (1990). “The more” and “the full”: on the reconstruction of Parmenides’ theory of sensation in Theophrastus, De Sensibus, 34. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 8, 118.Google Scholar
Laks, A. (2009). Aporia zero (Metaphysics, B 1, 995a24995b4). In Crubellier, M. & Laks, A., eds., Aristotle’s Metaphysics Beta. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2546.Google Scholar
Lamb, W. R. M. (1924). Plato. Laches, Protagoras, Meno, and Euthydemus. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lawrence, G. (2004). Reason, intention, and choice. An essay in practical philosophy. In Hear, A. O, ed., Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 265300.Google Scholar
Lear, J. (1988). Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lee, M.-K. (2005). Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343377.Google Scholar
Lewis, F. (1996). Self-knowledge in Aristotle. Topoi, 15(1), 3958.Google Scholar
Lewis, F. (2003). Is there room for Anaxagoras in an Aristotelian theory of mind? Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 25, 89129.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. (2007). The assimilation of sense to sense-object in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 33, 179220.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. (2009). Ancient theories of soul. In Zalta, E. N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University: Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved from: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/ancient-soulGoogle Scholar
Marmodoro, A. (2014). Aristotle on Perceiving Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McCready-Flora, I. C. (2013). Aristotle and the normativity of belief. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 44, 6798.Google Scholar
Mendell, H. (1998). Making sense of Aristotelian demonstration. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 16, 161225.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (1994). The origins of Aristotle’s concept of ἐνέργεια: ἐνέργεια and δύναμις. Ancient Philosophy, 14, 73114.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (2002). Aristotle’s definition of soul and the programme of the De Anima. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 22, 83139.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (2019). Physics I 1: the path to principles. In Ierodiakonou, K., Kalligas, P., & Karasmanis, V., eds., Aristotle’s Physics Alpha. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1952.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (2020). From De Anima III 4 to De Anima III 5. In Guyomarc’h, G., Louguet, C., & Murgier, C., eds., Aristote et l’Âme Humaine: Lectures de De Anima III offertes à Michel Crubellier. Leuven: Peeters, pp. 95155.Google Scholar
Mignucci, M. (1994). Truth and thought in the De Anima. In Alberti, A. M., ed., Realtà e Ragione. Studi di Filosofia Antica. Florence: Leo S. Olschki, pp. 137155.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. (2018). Aristotle. On the Soul and Other Psychological Works. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Newman, J. H. (1878). An Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine, 2nd edn. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Newman, J. H. (1889). An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent, 8th edn. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Perälä, M. (2018). Aristotle on perceptual discrimination. Phronesis, 63, 257292.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2017). Scientism and pseudoscience: in defense of demarcation projects. In Pigliucci, M. & Boudry, M., eds., Science Unlimited? The Challenges of Scientism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 185202.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. M. (2007). Aristotle’s De Anima. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Politis, V. (2001). Aristotle’s account of the intellect as pure capacity. Ancient Philosophy, 21(2), 375402.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. (2017). Aristotle. De Anima. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Rodier, G. (1900). Aristote. Traité De L’Âme, 2 vols. Paris: Leroux.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1924). Aristotle’s Metaphysics, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1961). Aristotle. De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rossi, G. (2017). Going through aporiai: the critical use of Aristotle’s dialectic. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 52, 209256.Google Scholar
Rovelli, C. (2015). Aristotle’s physics: a physicist’s look. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(1), 2340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sattler, B. (2017). Aristotle’s measurement dilemma. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 52, 257301.Google Scholar
Scaltsas, T. (1996). Biological matter and perceptual powers in Aristotle’s De Anima. Topoi, 14(1), 2537.Google Scholar
Shields, C. J. (2016). Aristotle. De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Silverman, A. (1989). Color and color-perception in Aristotle’s De Anima. Ancient Philosophy, 9(2), 271292.Google Scholar
Sisko, J. E. (1999). On separating the intellect from the body: Aristotle’s De Anima III. 4, 429a10b5. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 81(3), 249267.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1974). Body and soul in Aristotle. Philosophy, 49(1), 6389.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1995). Intentionality and physiological processes: Aristotle’s theory of sense‐perception. In Nussbaum, M. & Rorty, A. O., eds., Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 195226.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (2001). Aristotle on sensory processes and intentionality: a reply to Myles Burnyeat. In Perler, D., ed., Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality. Leiden: Brill, pp. 4961.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (2016). Measurement, theory of. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1st edn. London: Routledge. Retrieved from: www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/measurement-theory-of/v-1Google Scholar
Tracy, T. J. (1969). Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle. Chicago, IL: Loyola University Press.Google Scholar
Trendelenburg, F. A. (1877). Aristotelis De Anima Libri Tres. Berolini: W. Weberi.Google Scholar
Ward, J. K. (1988). Perception and λόγος in De Anima ii 12. Ancient Philosophy, 8(2), 217233.Google Scholar
Wedin, M. V. (1988). Mind and Imagination in Aristotle. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wieland, W. (1975). Aristotle’s Physics and the problem of inquiry into principles. In Barnes, J., Schofield, M., & Sorabji, R., eds., Articles on Aristotle, Vol. 1. Science. London: Duckworth, pp. 127140.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1981). The legacy of Greek philosophy. In Finley, M. I., ed., The Legacy of Greece: A New Appraisal. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 202255.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (2006). The legacy of Greek philosophy. In Burnyeat, M., ed., The Sense of the Past: Essays in the History of Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 348.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Sean Kelsey, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Mind and World in Aristotle's <i>De Anima</i>
  • Online publication: 16 December 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108966375.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Sean Kelsey, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Mind and World in Aristotle's <i>De Anima</i>
  • Online publication: 16 December 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108966375.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Sean Kelsey, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Mind and World in Aristotle's <i>De Anima</i>
  • Online publication: 16 December 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108966375.011
Available formats
×