Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-8kt4b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-20T20:58:48.174Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography of Rosenthal’s Works

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Josh Weisberg
Affiliation:
University of Houston
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Qualitative Consciousness
Themes from the Philosophy of David Rosenthal
, pp. 299 - 304
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

(2005). Consciousness and Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
(In press). Consciousness: A Reader, ed. with Weisberg, Josh, Wiley Publishing.Google Scholar
(1991). The Nature of Mind, anthology, ed., with six introductory essays, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2000). Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem, ed., 2nd ed. (anthology), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. 1st ed., Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hal, 1971.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

(2022). “Armstrong and Perception.” In Anstey, P. & Braddon-Mitchell, D. (eds), Armstrong’s Materialist Theory of the Mind (pp. 92–111), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2021). “The Extra Ingredient.” With Brown, R. & LeDoux, J. Biology & Philosophy, published online March 14. DOI: 10.1007/s10539-021-09797-zGoogle Scholar
(2020). “Assessing Criteria for Theories.” Cognitive Neuroscience, published online November 11.Google Scholar
(2020). “Competing Models of Consciousness.” Cognitive Neuropsychology 37 (March): 176–179. doi:10.1080/02643294.2020.1736536.Google Scholar
(2019). “Consciousness and Confidence.” Neuropsychologia 128 (May): 255–265.Google Scholar
(2019). “Chalmers’s Meta-Problem.” Special issue, Kammerer, F., Journal of Consciousness Studies 26(9–10): 194–204.Google Scholar
(2019). “Opportunities and Challenges for a Maturing Science of Consciousness.” With Michel, M., Lau, H., Fleming, S. M., et al, Nature Human Behaviour 3(2): 104–107.Google Scholar
(2019). “There’s Nothing about Mary.” In Coleman, C. (ed.), Classic Arguments: The Knowledge Argument (pp. 32–61), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(2018). “Misrepresentation and Mental Appearance.” Special edition, Pereira, A., Trans/Form/Ação 41: 49–74.Google Scholar
(2018). “Subjective Inflation: Phenomenology’s Get-Rich-Quick Scheme.” With Knotts, J. D. (lead), Odegaard, B. & Lau, H. Current Opinion in Psychology 29 (October): 49–55.Google Scholar
(2018). “Seeming to Seem.” In Huebner, B. (ed.), The Philosophy of Daniel Dennett (pp. 133–164), New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2017). “Measuring Away an Attentional Confound?.” With Morales, J., Mouradi, Y., Sergent, C., Block, N., Taschereau-Dumouchel, V., Grimaldi, P., & Lau, H., Neuroscience of Consciousness 3, 1 (August 2): nix019.Google Scholar
(2016). “Neural Antecedents of Spontaneous Voluntary Movement: A New Perspective.” With Schurger, A. & Mylopoulos, M., Trends in Cognitive Sciences 20, 2 (February): 77–79.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
(2016). “Quality Spaces, Relocation, and Grain.” In O’Shea, J. R. (ed.), Sellars and His Legacy (pp. 149–185), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2015). “Quality Spaces and Sensory Modalities.” In Coates, P. & Coleman, C. (eds), The Nature of Phenomenal Qualities: Sense, Perception, and Consciousness (pp. 35–65), Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2015). “Quality Space Theory in Olfaction.” In Young, B. D. & Keller, A. (eds), in the Olfactory Consciousness across Disciplines Research Topic, Frontiers in Consciousness Research, March, pp. 116–130.Google Scholar
(2014). “Consciousness Science: Real Progress and Lingering Misconceptions.” With Block, N., Carmel, D., Fleming, S. M., Kentridge, R. W., Koch, C., Lamme, V. A. F., & Lau, H., Trends in Cognitive Sciences 18, 11 (November): 566–567.Google Scholar
(2011). “Empirical Support for Higher-Order Theories of Conscious Awareness.” With Lau, H., Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15, 8 (August): 365–373.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
(2015). “Descartes’s Meditations on First Philosophy.” Untimely Reviews Series, Topoi 15, 2 (October): 541–548.Google Scholar
(2012). “Higher-Order Awareness, Misrepresentation, and Function.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 367, 1594 (May 19): 1424–1438.Google Scholar
(2012). “Awareness and Identification of Self.” In Liu, L. & Perry, J. (eds), Consciousness and the Self: New Essays (pp. 22–50), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
(2011). “The Higher-Order View Does Not Require Consciously Self-Directed Introspection: Response to Malach.” With Lau, H., Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15, 11 (November): 508–509.Google Scholar
(2011). “Exaggerated Reports: Reply to Block.” Analysis 71, 3 (July).Google Scholar
(2011). “The Mind and Its Expression.” In Rubenstein, E. M. & O’Shea, J. (eds), Self, Language, and Thought: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg (pp. 107–126), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishers.Google Scholar
(2010). “How to Think about Mental Qualities.” Philosophical Issues XX (October): 368–393.Google Scholar
(2010). “Consciousness, the Self, and Bodily Location.” Analysis 70, 1 (April).Google Scholar
(2008). “Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness.” With Weisberg, J., Scholarpedia 3, 5 (4407), http://scholarpedia.org/article/Higher-order_theories_of_consciousnessGoogle Scholar
(2010). “Expressing One’s Mind.” Acta Analytica 25, 1 (March): 21–34.Google Scholar
(2008). “Consciousness and Its Function.” Neuropsychologia 46(3): 829–840.Google Scholar
(2009). “Autobiographical and Disciplinary Reflections.” In Grim, P. (ed.), Mind and Consciousness: Five Questions (pp. 153–167), New York and London: Automatic Press.Google Scholar
(2009). “The Philosophical Study of Consciousness.” In Oxford Companion to Consciousness (pp. 522–529), Bayne, T., Cleeremans, A. & Wilken, P. (eds), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
(2009). “Concepts and Definitions of Consciousness.” In Banks, W. P. (ed.), Encyclopedia of Consciousness (pp. 157–169), Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
(2009). “Philosophy and Its Teaching.” In Talisse, R. & Eckert, M. (eds), A Teacher’s Life: Essays for Steven Cahn (pp. 67–83), Newton, NH: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
(2009). “Consciousness.” In Kim, J., Sosa, E. & Rosenkrantz, G. (eds), A Companion to Metaphysics, 2nd ed. (pp. 184–188), Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(2009). “Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness.” In McLaughlin, B. & Beckermann, A. (eds), Oxford Handbook in the Philosophy of Mind (pp. 239–252), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
(2008). “Freud and the Unconscious.” In Aryal, Y. (ed.), The Humanities at Work (pp. 221–230), Kathmandu, Nepal: Sunlight Publication.Google Scholar
(2007). “Phenomenological Overflow and Cognitive Access.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30, 5–6 (December): 522–523.Google Scholar
(2007). “Consciousness.” In The Language of Science (ISSN 1971–1352), ed. Sica, Giandomenico, Monza: Polimetrica, www.polimetrica.eu/site/?p=46Google Scholar
(2006). “Experience and the Physical.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 10–11 (October–November): 117–128.Google Scholar
(2006). “Consciousness.” Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 2, 2nd ed., London: Macmillan, pp. 449–458.Google Scholar
(2005). “Consciousness, Interpretation, and Higher-Order Thought.” In Giampieri-Deutsch, P. (ed.), Psychoanalysis as an Empirical, Interdisciplinary Science: Collected Papers on Contemporary Psychoanalytic Research (pp. 119–142), Vienna: Verlag der österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Austrian Academy of Sciences Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(2004). “Varieties of Higher-Order Theory.” In Gennaro, R. J. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness (pp. 17–44), Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishers.Google Scholar
(2004). “Review of Mark Rowlands, The Nature of Consciousness.” Mind 133, 451 (July): 581–588.Google Scholar
(2004). “Being Conscious of Ourselves.” The Monist 87, 2 (April), special issue on self-consciousness, edited by José Luis Bermúdez, 159–181.Google Scholar
(2004). “Subjective Character and Reflexive Content.” Book Symposium on John Perry’s Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68, 1 (January): 191–198.Google Scholar
(2003). “Unity of Consciousness and the Self.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103, 3 (April): 325–352.Google Scholar
(2002). “How Many Kinds of Consciousness?Consciousness and Cognition 11, 4 (December) (special ASSC5 issue edited by Güzeldere, G. and Mangun, R.): 653–665.Google Scholar
(2002). “Explaining Consciousness.” In Chalmers, D. J. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (pp. 406–421), New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2002). “The Timing of Conscious States.” Consciousness and Cognition 11, 2 (June): 215–220.Google Scholar
(2002). “Consciousness and Higher-Order Thought.” Macmillan Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science (pp. 717–726), Macmillan Publishers.Google Scholar
(2002). “Consciousness and the Mind.” Iyyun, The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 51, 3 (July): 227–251.Google Scholar
(2002). “Persons, Minds, and Consciousness.” In Auxier, R. E. & Lewis, E. Hahn, L. E. (eds), The Philosophy of Marjorie Grene, in The Library of Living Philosophers (pp. 199–220), Chicago and LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court.Google Scholar
(2002). “Moore’s Paradox and Crimmins’s Case.” Analysis 62, 2 (April): 167–171.Google Scholar
(2002). “The Higher-Order-Thought Model of Consciousness.” In Carter, R. (ed.), Consciousness (pp. 45–47), London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson; available as Exploring Consciousness, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2002.Google Scholar
(2001). “Consciousness and Sensation: Philosophical Aspects.” In Smelser, N. J. & Baltes, P. B. (eds), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences (pp. 2589–2596), 26 vols, Amsterdam: Pergamon/Elsevier.Google Scholar
(2001). “Color, Mental Location, and the Visual Field.” Consciousness and Cognition 10, 1 (March): 85–93.Google Scholar
(2000). “Introspection and Self-Interpretation.” Philosophical Topics 28, 2 (Fall) (special issue on introspection): 201–233.Google Scholar
(2000). “Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments.” Consciousness and Cognition 9, 2, Part 1 (June): 203–214.Google Scholar
(2000). “Metacognition and Higher-Order Thoughts.” Consciousness and Cognition 9, 2, Part 1 (June): 231–242.Google Scholar
(2000). “Content, Interpretation, and Consciousness.” In Ross, D., Brook, A. & Thompson, D. L. (eds), Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment (pp. 287–308), Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford Books.Google Scholar
(2000). “Consciousness and Metacognition.” In Sperber, D. (ed.), Metarepresentation: A Multidisciplinary Perspective (pp. 265–295), New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1999). “Sensory Quality and the Relocation Story.” Philosophical Topics 26, 1 and 2 (Spring and Fall): 321–350.Google Scholar
(1999). “The Colors and Shapes of Visual Experiences.” In Fisette, D. (ed.), Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution (pp. 95–118), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
(1998). “Consciousness and its Expression.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXII: 294–309.Google Scholar
(1998). “Introspection.” In Wilson, R. & Keil, F. C. (eds), MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (MITECS) (pp. 416–418), Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
(1998). “Dualism.” In Craig, E. (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 3 (pp. 133–138), London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
(1997). “Perceptual and Cognitive Models of Consciousness.” Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 45, 3 (Summer): 740–746.Google Scholar
(1997). “Apperception, Sensation, and Dissociability.” Mind and Language 12, 2 (June): 206–222.Google Scholar
(1997). “Phenomenal Consciousness and What It’s Like.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20, 1 (March): 64–65.Google Scholar
(1997). “A Theory of Consciousness.” In Block, N., Flanagan, O., & Güzeldere, G. (eds), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (pp. 729–753), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
(1996). “Consciousness and Higher-Order Thought.” Times of London Higher Education Supplement, April 5, p. iii.Google Scholar
(1995). “Multiple Drafts and Facts of the Matter.” In Metzinger, T. (ed.), Conscious Experience (pp. 275–290), Exeter: Imprint Academic,.Google Scholar
(1995). “Moore’s Paradox and Consciousness.” Philosophical Perspectives 9: 313–333.Google Scholar
(1995). “Self-Knowledge and Moore’s Paradox.” Philosophical Studies 77, 2–3, (March): 195–209.Google Scholar
(1995). “First-Person Operationalism and Mental Taxonomy.” Philosophical Topics 22, 1 and 2 (Spring and Fall): 319–349.Google Scholar
(1995). “Consciousness.” In Kim, J. & Sosa, E. (eds), A Companion to Metaphysics (pp. 92–94), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
(1994). “The Identity Theory.” In Guttenplan, S. (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (pp. 348–355), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
(1993). “State Consciousness and Transitive Consciousness.” Consciousness and Cognition 2, 4 (December): 355–363.Google Scholar
(1993). “Multiple Drafts and Higher-Order Thoughts.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LIII, 4 (December): 911–918.Google Scholar
(1993). “Thinking that One Thinks.” In Davies, M. & Humphreys, G. W. (eds), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays (pp. 197–223), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
(1993). “Higher-Order Thoughts and the Appendage Theory of Consciousness.” Philosophical Psychology VI, 2 (June): 155–167.Google Scholar
(1992). “Time and Consciousness.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15, 2 (June): 220–221.Google Scholar
(1992). “Consciousness, Plans, and Language.” Psycoloquy III 32 (June 3), http://psycprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000256/Google Scholar
(1992). “Review of The Disappearance of Introspection by William Lyons.” The Philosophical Review 101, 2 (April): 425–428.Google Scholar
(1991). “The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory Quality.” In Villanueva, E. (ed.), Consciousness: Philosophical Issues, 1 (pp. 15–36), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar
(1990). “On Being Accessible to Consciousness.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, 4 (December): 621–622.Google Scholar
(1989). “Philosophy and its History.” In Cohen, A. & Dascal, M. (eds), The Institution of Philosophy (pp. 141–176), Peru, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
(1988). “A Mean between Extremes: Ethical Theory and the Buck Trust Case.” Summation in Managers and Donors: The Buck Trust Case, Working Papers (pp. 95–109), New York: CUNY Graduate School and University Center, Spring.Google Scholar
(1988). Applied Ethics and Ethical Theory, a collection of original essays coedited with Shehadi, F. A., Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.Google Scholar
(1986). “Two Concepts of Consciousness.” Philosophical Studies 49, 3 (May): 329–359.Google Scholar
(1986). “Intentionality.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy X: 151–184. Reprinted, with postscript, in Silvers, S. (ed.), Rerepresentation: Readings in the Philosophy of Mental Representation (pp. 311–339, postscript, pp. 341–344), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989.Google Scholar
(1986). “Will and the Theory of Judgment.” In Rorty, A. O. (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations (pp. 405–434), Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
(1985). “Review of Perception: A Representative Theory, by Frank Jackson.” Journal of Philosophy 82, 1 (January): 28–41.Google Scholar
(1984). “The Behaviorist Concept of Mind.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7, 4 (December): 643–644.Google Scholar
(1984). “Armstrong’s Causal Theory of Mind.” In Bogdan, R. J. (ed.), Profiles: David Armstrong (pp. 79–120), Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.Google Scholar
(1983). “Emotions and the Self.” In Myers, G. E. & Irani, K. D. (eds), Emotion: Philosophical Studies (pp. 164–191), New York: Haven Publications.Google Scholar
(1983). “Review of Self-Awareness in Domesticated Animals.” ed. Wood-Gush, D. G. M., Dawkins, M. & Ewbank, R. (eds), Ethics and Animals 4, 3 (September): 90–93.Google Scholar
(1983). “Reductionism and Knowledge.” In Cauman, L. S., Levi, I., Parsons, C., & Schwartz, R. (eds), How Many Questions? Essays in Honor of Sidney Morgenbesser (pp. 276–300), Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
(1980). “Philosophy of Mind.” Social Research 47 (Winter): 789–802.Google Scholar
(1980). “Keeping Matter in Mind.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5: 295–322.Google Scholar
(1980). “The Modularity and Maturation of Cognitive Capacities.” Behavioral and Sciences 3, 1 (March): 32–34.Google Scholar
(1980). “Methodological Behaviorism: A Case for Transparent Taxonomy.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 1 (March): 92–93.Google Scholar
(1978). “The Insignificance of Incommensurate Variations.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1, 3 (September): 364.Google Scholar
(1976). “Possibility, Existence, and an Ontological Argument.” Philosophical Studies 30, 3 (September): 185–191.Google Scholar
(1976). “Mentality and Neutrality.” Journal of Philosophy 73, 13 (July 15): 386–415.Google Scholar
(1976). “Review of Res Cogitans, by Zeno Vendler.” Journal of Philosophy 73, 9 (May 6): 240–252.Google Scholar
(1976). “The Necessity of Foreknowledge.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy I: 22–25.Google Scholar
(1973). “Talking about Thinking.” Philosophical Studies 24, 5 (September): 283–313.Google Scholar
(1972). “The Rosenthal-Sellars Correspondence on Intentionality” (with Wilfrid Sellars). In Marras, A. (ed.), Intentionality, Mind, and Language (pp. 461–503), Urbana: University of Illinois Press, www.ditext.com/sellars/rsc.htmlGoogle Scholar
(1969). “Review of Memory, by Brian Smith.” Journal of Philosophy 66, 1 (January 16): 1722.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×