Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-22T06:13:28.128Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mental Imagery and the Epistemology of Testimony

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2022

Daniel Munro*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto, Department of Philosophy Toronto, Ontario, Canada
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Mental imagery often occurs during testimonial belief transmission: a testifier often episodically remembers or imagines a scene while describing it, while a listener often imagines that scene as it’s described to her. I argue that getting clear on imagery’s psychological roles in testimonial belief transmission has implications for some fundamental issues in the epistemology of testimony. I first appeal to imagery cases to argue against a widespread ‘internalist’ approach to the epistemology of testimony. I then appeal to the same sort of case to argue for an alternative, externalist view.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Canadian Journal of Philosophy

1. Introduction

It’s intuitive to think that during testimonial belief transmission, mental imagery often occurs in the minds of both testifier and listener, with the content of the listener’s imagery coming to resemble the content of the testifier’s imagery. To bring this out, consider a case:

BAD KITTY: Oliver hears a crash from the kitchen and goes to investigate. He finds a shattered vase on the floor next to the table it had previously been sitting on, as well as the cat jumping down from the table and bolting out of the room. Oliver’s wife, Esther, soon comes home to find Oliver cleaning up the vase. Oliver tells her, “The cat jumped on the table and knocked the vase to the floor. I came out to the kitchen and saw her looking startled as she sped out of the room.” Esther trusts Oliver’s testimony and takes what he says at face value.

Assume Oliver believes everything he says and testimonially transmits these beliefs to Esther.

To see how mental imagery might come into such a case, first consider the testifier, Oliver. Oliver in part describes things he witnessed firsthand: seeing the cat looking startled and speeding out of the kitchen. If we imagine ourselves in Oliver’s position as he recounts this experience, it seems he’d be recollecting what he witnessed in the form of an episodic memory while describing it. Oliver is also, in part, describing his reconstruction of events that occurred in the kitchen while he was in the bedroom: the cat jumping on the table and knocking the vase over. If we again put ourselves in Oliver’s shoes, it would seem natural for him to sensorily imagine this as he describes it as a way of mentally piecing together what he thinks happened. Next, consider Esther, the listener. We often imagine a scenario or event as we listen to testimony about it. We might expect Esther to be imagining the events Oliver describes, following along in her imagination with his descriptions.Footnote 1

So, mental imagery often occurs in the minds of both testifier and listener as a belief is transmitted from one mind to another. However, it’s not obvious exactly what role, if any, such imagery plays in the belief transmission process. On one hand, it seems possible that it’s purely epiphenomenal—that, for example, acquiring a testimonial belief merely causes Esther to form mental imagery rather than this imagery playing a psychological role in her belief formation. On the other hand, it’s striking that, as transmission occurs, Esther constructs a representation of the events Oliver describes that resembles the representations of those events before Oliver’s mind. Since testimonial transmission is a process in which information from one subject’s mind is conveyed to another’s, the fact that each comes to represent the world so similarly seems relevant to understanding the transmission process.Footnote 2

In this paper, I argue that getting clearer on imagery’s psychological roles in testimonial transmission has implications for some fundamental issues in the epistemology of testimony. I appeal to imagery cases of testimonial transmission to argue for a novel view about the justifying basis of testimonial beliefs—i.e., a novel view about the reason on the basis of which a listener forms a justified testimonial belief. On this view, the basis of a listener’s testimonial belief that P can, in at least some cases, be the testifier’s belief that P. In other words, a mental state in the mind of the testifier can serve as the basis of a belief in the mind of the listener. This is an ‘externalist’ account of the epistemology of testimony since it says factors external to a listener’s mind can count as the justifying basis of her belief. I appeal to imagery cases to argue for this view against a widespread ‘internalist’ approach to testimonial justification, on which only S’s own mental states can serve as the basis of her beliefs.

In section 2, I set up some general issues about the epistemology of testimony. I first describe what I take to be the standard internalist approach to theorizing about testimonial beliefs. On this approach, the basis of a testimonial belief always includes a mental state which represents the content of the testifier’s utterance. I then contrast the standard internalist approach with my alternative, externalist view, which I’ll call the ‘other minds approach.’

Section 3 appeals to empirical evidence about imagery’s psychological roles in testimonial belief acquisition to argue that the standard internalist approach fails to account for certain imagery cases. Section 4 then appeals to the same kind of imagery cases to argue against several alternatives to the standard internalist approach. Section 5 argues that the other minds approach gives a compelling account of these imagery cases. Section 6 extends the other minds approach from cases of successful belief transmission to cases in which a testifier intentionally misleads a listener, thereby revealing some interesting epistemological differences between the standard internalist approach and other minds approach. Finally, section 7 considers whether the other minds approach could be extended to nonimagery cases.

2. The basis of testimonial beliefs: Two approaches

2.a The standard internalist approach

This subsection first lays out the general internalist approach to epistemology, then explains the standard internalist approach to testimonial epistemology.

Internalists claim that a belief’s justification depends only on factors which are “internal” to a subject’s mind. This is most often cashed out as some version of the idea that a belief is justified by a subset of a subject’s nonfactive mental states (see, e.g., Feldman and Conee Reference Feldman and Conee2001; Wedgwood Reference Wedgwood2002; Huemer Reference Huemer2006; White Reference White, Dodd and Zardini2014). An internalist might hold, for example, that a perceptual belief that P is justified by one’s experience as of P, where experiences are characterized purely in terms of how things perceptually seem for the subject. Similarly, a belief that Q might be justified by the prior beliefs that P and that if P, then Q, where beliefs are characterized purely in terms of what a subject takes to be true.

Internalists (including those cited in the previous paragraph) often speak interchangeably about the mental factors which justify a belief and the basis of a belief. The basis of a belief is the reason (or set of reasons) on the basis of which one believes that P. So, to claim that a belief is justified by some nonfactive mental state(s) is equivalent to claiming that the state(s) in question is/are the reason(s) on the basis of which one formed the belief. One’s perceptual experience as of P, for example, can be the reason on the basis of which one believes that P.

I’ll assume the orthodox, widespread view of epistemic basing which says the basis of a belief is the reason which caused that belief. Combined with the internalist commitments just sketched, this yields the view that the basis of S’s belief is S’s mental state(s) which caused S’s belief. While there are many available accounts of basing that incorporate additional conditions besides causation, it’s very common to include a causal condition at least as a necessary condition, even if not a sufficient one (for overviews of the literature, see Korez Reference Korez1997 and Sylvan Reference Sylvan2016). And, as we’ll see below, proponents of the standard internalist view of testimony discuss basing in terms of causation, in line with this view. Since both my negative and positive arguments in this paper will primarily concern this causal component of basing, they’ll apply to any account that includes causation as a necessary condition even if they also include other necessary conditions.Footnote 3

I turn now to the family of views I’ll call the ‘standard internalist approach’ to the epistemology of testimony, which I take to be the paradigmatic internalist way of understanding the justifying basis of testimonial beliefs. These views hold, in line with the broader internalist tradition, that the basis of a testimonial belief includes only mental states of the listener. In particular, they hold that it includes a mental state which somehow represents the content of the testifier’s utterance. From that starting point, there are various ways of developing this standard internalist approach. Since it’s the main approach I aim to replace with my alternative, externalist account, it’s worth spelling out some versions of this approach in detail.

Perhaps the most common are what we might call ‘doxastic’ versions of the approach. These views say that in the process of acquiring a testimonial belief that P, one first forms a belief that a testifier said that P; one then comes to believe P (at least in part) on the basis of one’s belief that the testifier said that P. In other words, one’s belief that the testifier said that P is among the mental states which causes one to believe P.

Malmgren (Reference Malmgren2006) gives one statement of such a view. She says:

[S]uppose John tells me that it is raining, and that I … gain knowledge by (John’s) testimony that it is raining. If you asked me how I know that it is raining, then presumably part of my (pretheoretical) answer would be: ‘John told me,’ ‘John said so,’ or ‘John said that it is raining’ … What my answer brings out is that part of my reason for believing that it is raining is that John said so. But that is just to say that my warranted (or knowledgeable) belief about what John said plays an epistemic role in the formation of my knowledge that it is raining. (225)

Malmgren also claims that this specifically involves the belief about what the testifier said causing one’s knowledge (sec. 7), and that this talk of “knowledge” is really elliptical for talk of belief (225n56). So, she takes it that a testimonial belief that P is caused (at least in part) by one’s belief that a testifier said that P.

Barnett (Reference Barnett2015) also endorses a doxastic version of the standard internalist approach. He first claims that “when a source of testimony tells you that P, what you learn first is not P itself but instead merely the fact that the source says that P”; subsequently, “on the basis of what you learn first”—i.e., that the speaker said that P—you’re justified in believing that P (356–57). Barnett later writes about the basing relation in terms of causal relations between beliefs (378–79). So, it’s clear his considered view is that the basis of one’s testimonial belief that P includes the belief that S said that P.

Fricker (Reference Fricker1987) is also plausibly read as endorsing a doxastic version of the standard internalist approach. As a general necessary condition for justification, Fricker argues that a “subject’s belief must be causally dependent on his belief in (or some kind of sub-doxastic registering of) propositions … which, if articulated, would constitute a good argument for it” (61). She then argues, in line with the standard internalist approach, that the causes of justified testimonial beliefs include “a belief that the speaker has made an assertion with a particular content” (69–70).

We can also formulate ‘nondoxastic’ versions of the standard internalist approach. On these views, the basis of a testimonial belief includes some nondoxastic grasp of the meaning of an utterance. We can generate versions of the standard internalist approach by substituting in any such view of language comprehension. For example, Longworth (Reference Longworth2018) argues that comprehending an utterance “P” involves, rather than a belief about what a speaker said, a first-order attitude towards P, something akin to entertaining P. He then argues that a listener moves from understanding an utterance to accepting its content, a process of forming a belief “on the basis of having understood” the utterance (829).

There are other nondoxastic views of comprehension to which we could appeal to flesh out the standard internalist approach. For example, perceptual views of comprehension hold that, when we hear an utterance, we literally hear the meaning of that utterance (Fricker Reference Fricker and Barber2003; Brogaard Reference Brogaard2018). Such views aren’t necessarily developed as accounts of the basis of testimonial beliefs, but it’s easy to see how we could position them as such, along the same lines as Longworth’s account.

So, various epistemologists endorse some version of the standard internalist approach.Footnote 4 Furthermore, it makes sense to call this the ‘standard’ internalist approach because it’s simply a natural way of applying internalist ideas to testimony. Epistemologists—both internalist and externalist—often claim that, intuitively, it seems natural to cite the fact that a testifier said that P when asked about the reasons for one’s testimonial beliefs (Fricker Reference Fricker1987; Malmgren Reference Malmgren2006; Nagel Reference Nagel, Brown and Simion2021). If internalists want to accept this intuition, they must give a mentalistic interpretation of it. It seems natural to construe it as indicating that one’s testimonial belief that P was caused by a mental state representing what the testifier said. (I agree that this evidence is prima facie intuitively compelling, even though I ultimately argue against this approach.)

Proponents of the standard internalist approach differ as to exactly what else is included in the justifying basis of testimonial beliefs, besides agreeing that it includes a representation of the content of the testifier’s utterance.Footnote 5 However, my arguments in section 3 will aim to undermine any view which accepts this point, so I needn’t go into detail about other conditions they endorse.

2.b The other minds approach

This paper defends an alternative to the standard internalist approach, one on which the basis of a listener’s testimonial belief needn’t include only the listener’s mental states. Instead, the listener’s testimonial belief that P can be based (at least in part) on the testifier’s belief that P. In other words, the testifier’s belief can be among the reasons which cause the listener’s belief. I call this view the ‘other minds approach,’ since it says the basis of a listener’s belief can be located in another person’s mind. (Hereafter, for simplicity, I’ll refer to the other minds approach as the view that testifier’s belief can be the basis of the listener’s belief, though I leave open whether other factors are also included in that basis.)

I’ll remain neutral about the precise scope of the other minds approach. I’ll only argue that, contrary to the standard internalist approach, there are at least some cases in which the testifier’s belief is the basis of the listener’s testimonial belief. I therefore won’t take a stance on whether the internalist approach fails as an account of every single case of testimonial belief, as opposed to merely failing in certain cases. Even so, the other minds approach is quite a departure from the internalist way of conceiving the basing relation on which the basis of one’s belief must be a mental state in one’s own mind.

In section 5, I’ll defend the other minds approach by considering cases in which a listener constructs mental imagery which resembles the imagery before the testifier’s mind. I’ll motivate the approach by considering the nature of the causal relationship between each subject’s mental imagery. Considering this relationship reveals that a relationship of basing holds between the listener’s testimonial belief that P and the testifier’s belief that P, since the relationship between their beliefs exhibits certain characteristic properties of basing.Footnote 6

It might be tempting to think that the other minds approach is dead on arrival since the testifier’s belief is so far down the causal chain from the listener’s. Philosophers sometimes argue that the basis of a belief includes only proximate causes of that belief (cf. Wedgwood Reference Wedgwood2002; Turri Reference Turri2011). However, it seems there are many causal intermediaries between the testifier’s belief and the listener’s: the testifier’s speech, the listener’s perception of that speech, the listener’s comprehension of what was said, and perhaps the listener’s belief that the testifier said that P. So, one might claim that the testifier’s belief is too far removed from the listener’s to be its basis.

My goal is to close this apparent epistemological gap between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs, at least in certain cases involving mental imagery. I’ll argue across sections 34 that, in certain such cases, no causal intermediary between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs is part of the listener’s justifying basis. Furthermore, I’ll argue that the causal relationship which holds between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs has the right properties to count as a basing relationship.

The first step is to argue, in the next section, that the standard internalist approach fails to account for the relevant imagery cases.

3. Problem cases for the standard internalist approach

Section 3.a first appeals to empirical work on mental imagery and language comprehension to give an account of imagery’s role in comprehending testimony. Section 3.b then argues that the same mental imagery involved in comprehension can serve as the format of a listener’s testimonial belief. Section 3.c argues that, furthermore, a single process of mental imagery construction can simultaneously serve as both the means of comprehending testimony and of forming a testimonial belief. Finally, section 3.d argues that the internalist approach can’t account for cases where imagery serves both these roles simultaneously.Footnote 7

In identifying certain psychological roles for mental imagery in testimonial belief acquisition, I don’t mean to imply that all cases of testimonial belief acquisition work this way or involve mental imagery. Instead, I merely aim to characterize a particular kind of case in which mental imagery is involved.

3.a Mental imagery in testimonial comprehension

Section 2 described some nondoxastic accounts of testimonial comprehension—accounts on which we comprehend an utterance “P” by, for example, entertaining or perceiving its meaning. Recent empirical work on language comprehension suggests one specific way in which we often nondoxastically comprehend testimony: by constructing mental imagery of the situation described by that testimony. This involves grasping the content the testifier has expressed by constructing mental imagery representing it. In BAD KITTY, for example, Oliver’s utterance “the cat jumped on the table and knocked over the vase” causes Esther to construct a mental image representing the state of affairs he describes, and she thereby grasps the meaning of his utterance.Footnote 8

Evidence for this form of comprehension comes from psycholinguistic studies of speech and text comprehension, on the basis of which its widely accepted that comprehension often involves mentally constructing a “situation model” of the scene described. At least in the kind of case I’m focused on, cases like BAD KITTY, such models are typically taken to be imagistic in format (Fincher-Kiefer Reference Fincher-Kiefer2001; Kurby and Zacks Reference Kurby and Zacks2013; Zwaan Reference Zwaan2016). As an interlocutor describes a situation to us, they prompt us to construct an imagistic representation of that situation, which is updated and modified as the conversation continues. We grasp the content a testifier has asserted by representing it in mental imagery.Footnote 9

Fincher-Kiefer (Reference Fincher-Kiefer2001) provides classic experimental evidence for thinking mental imagery can be involved in comprehension, as opposed to merely co-occurring with it. She hypothesizes that, if comprehending a story involves constructing mental imagery, then comprehension would be disrupted when subjects simultaneously engage in another task involving imagery—for example, holding some other, unrelated image in mind while reading. That’s because if their capacity to construct imagery is already in use for some other task, it can’t be fully recruited for comprehension. Fincher-Kiefer found that subjects’ comprehension is disrupted significantly more when engaging in simultaneous imagery tasks than when engaging in simultaneous verbal, nonimagery tasks, supporting the idea that imagery is involved in comprehension.

On the basis of such evidence, empirical researchers posit that situation modelling serves various functional roles related to discourse comprehension. For example, it allows one to connect a testifier’s references to particular objects to one’s own stored mental representations of those objects. In BAD KITTY, Oliver’s references to “the vase,” “the “cat,” and “the kitchen” activate imagistic mental representations of those objects that Esther has stored from past experiences, allowing her to comprehend which particular objects Oliver is referring to. Situation models also allow one to mentally organize the individual elements of a scene into the particular spatiotemporal organization a testifier is describing, thus constructing an overall, coherent representation of that scene.

By playing comprehension-related roles like this, situation models ground the distinction between perceiving a testifier’s particular words or utterances and comprehending what the testifier said about the world. In addition to perceptually experiencing an act of testifying, we comprehend that testimony by imaginatively representing the world as described by it.

Now, one might object that we can’t comprehend speech (a propositional representation) by forming mental imagery (often described as an “imagistic” or “iconic” representation rather than propositional). On this objection, since speech has propositional content while imagery has imagistic content, it doesn’t make sense to say we represent the content of an utterance in mental imagery.

However, there are various ways of responding to this objection. For one, we might just respond that mental images really can be vehicles for propositional content. This propositional view of mental imagery content is quite controversial (cf. Nanay Reference Nanay2015; Pearson and Kosslyn Reference Pearson and Kosslyn2015). However, it coheres well with a broader picture many accept, on which other perceptually formatted representations have propositional content, including perceptual experience (e.g., Dretske Reference Dretske1997; Byrne Reference Byrne2009) and episodic memory (e.g., Fernández Reference Fernández2006; Byrne Reference Byrne2010). If one accepts this broader picture, then this response seems promising.

Alternatively, one might argue that the propositional/imagistic distinction merely concerns the format of representations rather than their content. As Nanay (Reference Nanay and Zalta2021, sec. 1.5) argues, it seems representations in these distinct formats can represent the same content—that, for example, the utterance “the cat broke the vase” can represent the same state of affairs as a mental image of the cat breaking the vase. If that’s true, a mental image could be a way of comprehending the same content a testifier conveyed in their speech.

In what follows, I remain neutral between these two responses to the foregoing objection.

3.b Mental imagery as format of testimonial belief

In addition to their role in comprehension, situation models are also often the representations we commit to long-term memory when retaining information about the world gleaned from testimony. In other words, rather than remembering a testifier’s specific words or utterances, we often instead store a situation model of the situation they described to us (Zwaan and Radvansky Reference Zwaan and Radvansky1998; Zacks, Mar, and Calarco Reference Zacks, Mar, Calarco, Schober, Rapp and Britt2018; McClelland et al. Reference McClelland, Hill, Rudolph, Baldridge and Schütze2019).

Evidence for this comes from classic studies such as those by Bransford, Barclay, and Franks (Reference Bransford, Barclay and Franks1972). In one such study, subjects first listened to a set of sentences being read to them, including one of the following:

  1. (1) Three turtles rested on a floating log, and a fish swam beneath them.

  2. (2) Three turtles rested beside a floating log, and a fish swam beneath it.

Later, subjects were asked to identify which sentences on a second list they recognized as having heard previously. This second list included one of the following:

  1. (3) Three turtles rested on a floating log, and a fish swam beneath it.

  2. (4) Three turtles rested beside a floating log, and a fish swam beneath them.

Notice that while all of these sentences are superficially very similar (cf. Glenberg, Meyer, and Lindem Reference Glenberg, Meyer and Lindem1987), the scenes described by (1) and (3) are the same, while (2) and (4) each describe scenes distinct from the rest. When asked to recall which sentences they recognize, subjects who’d earlier heard (1) are highly likely to mistakenly say they recognize (3), while they can much more easily discriminate between all other pairs of sentences.

The standard explanation of such results is that subjects don’t tend to retain and then recollect a representation of a speaker’s particular words or utterances. Instead, they store a situation model of the scene described by those utterances. When listening to the second set of sentences, they then retrieve this stored situation model as a means of determining whether they previously heard any of those sentences.

The kind of case just described involves committing to memory information about a toy, fictional scene—one doesn’t actually take the world to be such that three turtles sat on a log while a fish swam beneath them. However, we can apply the same kind of distinction between storing a representation of the speaker’s words and storing a situation model of the scene these words describe to cases like BAD KITTY, where what’s described is instead the actual world. We can distinguish Esther storing a representation of Oliver’s utterances, such as “the cat knocked over the vase,” from Esther storing a representation of the scene Oliver’s utterances describe, i.e., the cat knocking over the vase. The difference between this case and the turtle/fish case is that Esther isn’t storing a representation of a fictional scenario. Instead, Esther is storing a representation of the way the world is, as learned from Oliver’s testimony. Committing a situation model to memory is therefore a way for her to remember the fact that the cat knocked over the vase, information acquired when Oliver’s testimony prompted her to imagine this scene.

This suggests that, in addition to its role in comprehension, such mental imagery can also be the format of a listener’s testimonial belief. That’s because this imagery plays the same functional role that we’d assign to a belief acquired from testimony. Acquiring a testimonial belief is a process of acquiring some information about the world from a testifier, after which one can store this belief and have it available for later retrieval. And, in the kind of case I just described, one doesn’t comprehend testimony via mental imagery and then subsequently form and store a distinct representation or belief. Instead, the situation model constructed in response to testimony is the format in which one acquires and retains information from testimony—it’s the means by which one adds information gleaned from testimony to one’s existing set of information about the world. So, we should take such imaginative representations to be a listener’s testimonial beliefs.Footnote 10

My argument here assumes that beliefs can be imagistic. This is controversial but does have various adherents (Kaplan Reference Kaplan1968; Van Leeuwen Reference Van Leeuwen2013; Langland-Hassan Reference Langland-Hassan2020). My view is that once we recognize that imagistic situation models can play the functional role of testimonial beliefs, this gives us a positive reason to accept that beliefs can be imagistic, at least in relevant cases.

One might object that beliefs are propositional attitudes while mental images are nonpropositional. There are at least two ways we might respond. If the propositional/imagistic distinction is taken to concern content, then we might argue mental images do in fact have propositional content (see the end of Section 3.a for more on this view). Alternatively, if the propositional/imagistic distinction concerns format rather than content (see again the end of Section 3.a), we might argue that the considerations I’ve given in this section reveal some beliefs are nonpropositional after all. I’ll remain neutral between these responses.Footnote 11

3.c Comprehension and belief formation as simultaneous

When the very same instance of mental imagery is involved in both comprehending testimony and forming a testimonial belief, can we both comprehend and acquire a belief from testimony simultaneously via a single process of constructing that imagery? Or, must we always first comprehend testimony by constructing mental imagery and then, subsequently, accept or assent to the content of this imagery as true, only after which it becomes a belief? I think it’s plausible that the two are often simultaneous due to the role of trust in acquiring testimonial beliefs.

I’ll adopt Nguyen’s (Reference NguyenForthcoming) account of trust as an unquestioning attitude. Nguyen argues that trust needn’t involve an explicit attitude towards a testifier, nor a conscious decision to trust a testifier. Instead, trusting a testifier often involves a disposition to accept what she says as true without deliberating about it or pausing to evaluate her testimony’s merits. In other words, accepting trusted testimony simply involves a lack of actively questioning or deliberating. In this sense, Nguyen argues that our relationship to those we trust is very much like our relationship to our own cognitive faculties. Unless we’re aware of a reason not to, we’re disposed to simply treat the information delivered by these faculties, such as perception and memory, at face value. Likewise, trusting a testifier involves being disposed to immediately accept the content of her testimony as true with no intervening checking or deliberation.Footnote 12

Sometimes, we initially distrust a testifier, or we’re initially unsure about whether to trust her. Often, though, we already trust a testifier prior to receiving testimony. I’ll assume that this is the case in BAD KITTY: that Esther already trusts Oliver before receiving his testimony. (It’s controversial how often we trust testifiers prior to receiving their testimony; for my purposes, all that matters is that we do so at least sometimes, which seems accurate at least in the context of close personal relationships.)

If a listener already trusts a testifier—i.e., is predisposed to simply take her at her word—then we should expect her to automatically add the content of that testifier’s word to her existing store of beliefs about the world (cf. McDowell Reference McDowell, Matilal and Chakrabarti1994; Westra and Nagel Reference Westra and Nagel2021). This seems to fit with the phenomenology of accepting trusted testimony. Imagine being Esther in a case of trust like BAD KITTY in comparison with this case:

SUSPICIOUS ESTHER: Oliver tells Esther, “The cat jumped on the table and knocked the vase to the floor.” Because Esther knows Oliver is clumsy and has a track record of lying about breaking things around the house, she suspects he might be trying to cover up the fact that he broke the vase himself. She’s therefore hesitant to accept what he tells her and suspends judgment.

Here, Esther could still comprehend Oliver’s testimony by engaging in situation modelling for the purpose of mere comprehension. But what distinguishes this case from BAD KITTY is that she uses mental imagery merely to entertain what Oliver tells her rather than trusting him and therefore automatically accepting what he says at face value.

Now, if testimonial comprehension and belief formation were distinct states or processes, we might expect automatic, trusted acceptance to involve the former process automatically causing the latter. That would be a version of the standard internalist approach on which comprehension of a speaker’s utterance causes a testimonial belief, thus serving as its basis. So, on their own, these considerations about the nature of trust don’t suggest anything about the causal relationship between comprehension and belief formation.

However, in cases involving imagery, these considerations about trust give us reason to think comprehension and belief formation can occur simultaneously. In BAD KITTY, Esther’s construction of mental imagery can be both the process by which she comprehends Oliver’s testimony and the process by which she forms a testimonial belief. If Esther is predisposed to take Oliver’s word at face value, then there’s no reason to think she must first comprehend his testimony and then form a testimonial belief. That’s because if the same imagery serves both roles, it would be psychologically redundant to first entertain the content of his testimony and then, subsequently, accept it. Instead, we should expect that Esther’s construction of imagery is simultaneously a process of comprehending Oliver’s testimony and of forming a belief. In other words, since Esther is already disposed to accept what Oliver says before he even says it, the imagistic process by which she comprehends his testimony will already be a process of adding the information he transmits into her existing store of information about the world.

Of course, it’s ultimately an empirical question whether such construction of mental imagery ever simultaneously functions as both the process of comprehension and the process of belief formation. But my point is that we have theoretical reason to think the two can occur simultaneously based on philosophical considerations about trust. If a listener trusts a testifier, it would be psychologically redundant to engage in two, distinct steps, since both comprehension and belief formation involve the same mental imagery. Unless we have good reason to favor a more complex theory, we should opt for a more simplistic theory over one that posits multiple, psychologically redundant processes.

To sum up this section so far: there are cases of testimonial belief acquisition in which the construction of mental imagery serves simultaneously as both the means of comprehension and the formation of a listener’s belief. I next argue that the standard internalist approach to conceptualizing the basis of testimonial beliefs cannot account for such cases.

3.d Against the standard internalist approach

The standard internalist approach says that a listener first represents the content of a testifier’s utterance either via a belief that the testifier said that P or via some nondoxastic way of grasping that content. This mental state then serves as (part of) the basis of the listener’s testimonial belief. On an orthodox, casual picture of the nature of basing, this means the listener’s mental state causes her testimonial belief. However, I now argue that this internalist approach cannot apply to cases on which imagery simultaneously serves as the process of both comprehending testimony and of forming a testimonial belief.

It should be clear why these cases preclude a picture on which a listener nondoxastically comprehends what was said and this causes her testimonial belief. In the relevant cases, the construction of mental imagery is the process by which we simultaneously comprehend testimony and acquire a testimonial belief. But if this same process serves both of these roles simultaneously, then there’s no point where a listener’s comprehension causes her belief. Since the basis of a belief is its cause, it can’t be that one’s nondoxastic comprehension of what was said is part of the basis of one’s belief.

Such cases also pose counterexamples to doxastic versions of the standard internalist approach, where a listener’s belief that a testifier said that P causes her testimonial belief that P. That’s because a listener has to comprehend an utterance before she forms a belief about what was said—one can’t form a belief that a testifier said that P without comprehending the testifier’s utterance “P.” But, again, the process of comprehending testimony is, in the cases I’ve considered, simultaneously the process of forming a testimonial belief. If comprehension must come before a belief about what was said, and if comprehension and testimonial belief formation occur simultaneously, then testimonial belief formation also comes before a belief about what was said. It therefore can’t be that one’s belief about what a testifier said causally precedes one’s testimonial belief.

The various versions of the standard internalist approach thus assume a picture of the psychology of testimonial belief formation which doesn’t apply to the imagery cases I’m considering.

4. Other causal intermediaries between minds

The previous section opened up some room to argue for the other minds approach (according to which the testifier’s belief can be the basis of the listener’s belief) by rejecting the standard internalist approach. However, the basis of a belief is often thought to be causally very proximate to it. This might seem like a barrier to accepting the other minds approach, since the testifier’s belief seems causally remote from the listener’s. Before arguing directly for the other minds approach in section 5, this section removes this barrier.

The previous section considered two potential causal intermediaries between the testifier’s belief and the listener’s: the listener’s belief that the testifier said that P and the listener’s nondoxastic comprehension of a testifier’s utterance. However, if there are other causal intermediaries that could serve as part of the listener’s basis, then it might seem we should try to develop our account in terms of these. In this section, I walk through several of these intermediaries, arguing that none of them count as part of the listener’s basis.

4.a Belief that the testifier believes that P

The other minds approach holds that the listener’s belief that P can be based on the testifier’s belief that P. However, one might object that the listener’s belief that the testifier believes that P is more causally proximate to her testimonial belief. So, an alternative view says that in forming a testimonial belief, the listener first learns about what the testifier believes. Then, this belief that the testifier believes that P is among the causes of the testimonial belief that P.

However, in the kind of imagery cases I considered in the previous section, the listener’s belief about what a testifier believes cannot be among the causes of her testimonial belief. Before the listener can form a belief about what the testifier believes, she first has to comprehend the testifier’s utterance: since an utterance serves to express the testifier’s belief, it’s only by comprehending the utterance that the listener learns what the testifier believes. So, comprehending an utterance must be causally prior to forming a belief about what the testifier believes. In the cases I’m considering, though, comprehension is simultaneous with forming a testimonial belief. Thus, in these cases, forming a testimonial belief that P must be prior to forming a belief that the testifier believes that P. So, it can’t be that a belief about what the testifier believes causes the listener’s testimonial belief.

4.b Perceptual experience of the testifier’s utterance

There’s a causal line that proceeds from the testifier’s belief, through the testifier’s utterance, through the listener’s perception of that utterance, to the listener’s imagery (i.e., the listener’s belief). So, it seems that the listener’s perceptual experience of the testifier’s utterance is a mental state that’s causally proximate to her testimonial belief. Thus, another potential alternative to the standard internalist approach is to give an account of the listener’s basis in terms of this experience. However, I now argue that in the imagery cases I’m focused on, the listener’s experience isn’t part of her justifying basis.

First, note that if this experience is part of the listener’s justification for her belief, it must be so in the sense that it’s part of an inference from this experience to her belief. That’s because the contents of one’s experience of a testifier’s utterances are quite distinct from the contents one ends up believing. In BAD KITTY, for example, Esther auditorily perceives Oliver uttering strings of words that form sentences (e.g., “the cat knocked the vase to the floor”), while she acquires a testimonial belief not about words, sentences, or utterances, but about the situation Oliver describes (the cat knocking the vase to the floor).

A justified transition from the perception of an utterance “P” to a belief that P would therefore require something in addition to the mere perception of the utterance—something more like an inference that includes additional premises connecting the content of one’s perception to the content of one’s testimonial belief. Such premises might include, for example, one’s linguistic knowledge about what the testifier’s words mean or evidence from the meanings of past similar utterances one experienced that would allow one to justifiably infer one’s testimonial belief. Suppose, for example, that one knows from past experience that an utterance “P” has the function of presenting proposition P as true; based on this knowledge, in conjunction with one’s present experience of a testifier uttering “P,” one might then justifiably infer P.

Now, I take it as intuitively clear that Esther’s belief in BAD KITTY is justified as long as she has no reason to think Oliver is untrustworthy or that his testimony is misleading.Footnote 13 So, if the justifying basis of Esther’s testimonial belief is to include her perception of Oliver’s utterance, this basis must also include other premises that allow her to justifiably infer her testimonial belief from her perception of this utterance. However, I’ll now argue that, in the kind of imagery case on which I’m focused, it’s implausible that we go through an inferential process to transition from perceiving a testifier’s speech to acquiring a testimonial belief.

As Burge (Reference Burge1993) points out about testimony in general, introspective evidence suggests we don’t go through any kind of inferential process to transition from perceiving a testifier’s speech to comprehending it; rather, such transitions seem quite fast and automatic.Footnote 14 According to my account of relevant imagery cases in section 3, comprehending testimony is simultaneous with acquiring a belief from it via a single process of imagery construction. So, if Burge is right that the transition from hearing a testifier’s speech to comprehending it is merely causal rather than inferential, the same would go, in these cases, for the transition from hearing the testifier’s speech to forming a testimonial belief.

Now, Burge’s opponents have pointed out that this introspective evidence isn’t airtight: it’s plausible that many of our everyday inferences are based on tacit or implicit premises rather than performed in an explicit, consciously introspectable way (Christensen and Kornblith Reference Christensen and Kornblith1997; Malmgren Reference Malmgren2006). However, empirical facts about the relation between perceiving speech and perceptual processing help support Burge’s view in my imagery cases.

Both behavioural and brain-imaging evidence suggest that perceiving speech rapidly and automatically modulates perceptual processing such that the brain automatically begins constructing perceptual representations of objects referred to in speech (Lupyan and Clark Reference Lupyan and Clark2015; Boutonnet and Lupyan Reference Boutonnet and Lupyan2015). Importantly, this includes the modulation of very low-level perceptual areas typically thought to be encapsulated from conscious reasoning or inferential processes. So, for example, hearing the word ‘cat’ cues the visual system to expect to see a cat even before one has been visually presented with a cat. This amounts to the brain automatically beginning to construct a visual representation of a cat prior to perceiving a cat, which then has measurable effects in terms of speed and performance on object recognition and perceptual discrimination tasks.

This sort of mechanism plausibly also explains why the brain automatically constructs mental imagery in response to perceiving speech, as in the kinds of testimony cases I’m considering (Clark Reference Clark2016, chap. 3; Jones and Wilkinson Reference Jones, Wilkinson and Abraham2020). Sensory imagining involves constructing perceptual representations in absence of stimuli. So, if our brains automatically construct perceptual representations in response to speech, we should expect this to result in conscious mental imagery in cases where one isn’t presented with a relevant stimulus (e.g., where one hears a description of some object or scene but that object or scene isn’t currently present to be perceived). In the kinds of cases I’ve been discussing, this seems intuitive and phenomenologically apt: when listening to a testifier triggers mental imagery, this imagery often occurs automatically and unreflectively. This is explained by the fact that, when speech triggers perceptual processing, this is an automatic and noninferential process rather than a personal-level, inferential one.

So, in my imagery cases, the transition from perceiving a testifier’s speech to acquiring a testimonial belief is a noninferential one, a merely causal transition that occurs when the perception of speech automatically activates mental imagery. I argued above that if the listener’s experience is part of what justifies her belief, this would require additional, inferential steps linking the content of the experience to the content of the testimonial belief. So, a listener’s experience of a testifier’s utterances isn’t part of the justifying basis of her testimonial belief.

4.c The testifier’s utterance

Again, there’s a causal line that proceeds from the testifier’s belief, through the testifier’s utterances, through the listener’s experience of those utterances, to the listener’s imagery. So, the remaining causal intermediary that might count as part of the listener’s basis is the testifier’s utterance itself. (This is already quite a departure from the internalist approach, since it cites a cause that isn’t one of the listener’s mental states.)

However, the same arguments I just gave in section 4.b regarding the listener’s experience of the testifier’s utterance can easily be extended to the testifier’s utterance itself. If the content of the listener’s experience of the utterance doesn’t justify the listener’s belief, then neither does that utterance itself, since the content of one’s experience just is that utterance. So, assuming Esther’s testimonial belief is justified in BAD KITTY, we can’t appeal to Oliver’s utterance in an account of the basis of her belief.

5. In defense of the other minds approach

This section defends the other minds approach, an externalist alternative to the standard internalist approach. On this approach, a listener’s testimonial belief that P can be based on the testifier’s belief that P, meaning the listener’s basis can be a mental state in another person’s mind.

So far, I’ve mainly considered mental imagery in testimonial belief formation. This section builds up to arguing for the other minds approach by first considering imagery’s role across the testimonial transmission process, from the mind of the testifier to the mind of the listener. Section 5.a considers the role of mental imagery in the mind of the testifier, i.e., in the production of testimony. I argue that the listener’s mental imagery can be the format of the belief the listener brings to mind and then transmits to the listener. Section 5.b then characterizes the intimate causal relationship that, in relevant cases, holds between the mental imagery in both subjects’ minds. Since the mental imagery in each mind is the format of each subject’s belief, this amounts to characterizing the causal relationship between their beliefs. Section 5.c then argues that this causal relationship is a relationship of basing, thus defending the other minds approach.

5.a Imagery in the production of testimony

Section 1 noted that mental imagery often occurs in the mind of the testifier while producing descriptions of some scene. In BAD KITTY, we’d expect Oliver to episodically remember the events he perceived firsthand as he describes them, as well as imagine the events he mentally reconstructed. Neuroimaging evidence suggests such imagery does often occur: producing a narrative or descriptions of a scene often involves visualization and other imagery-construction processes, either episodic remembering or imagining (Mar Reference Mar2004; Zadbood et al. Reference Zadbood, Chen, Leong, Norman and Hasson2017).

What role, exactly, does this imagery play in the process of producing testimony? Plausibly, a testifier like Oliver “reads off” descriptions of a scene from the mental imagery before his mind. Episodic memory allows one to bring to mind a rich representation of an event via a mental image which recreates one’s experience of the event and contains various information about it. One can then select particular elements of a memory image’s contents to report, describing them in one’s utterances (cf. Koriat and Goldsmith Reference Koriat and Goldsmith1996; Mahr and Csibra Reference Mahr and Csibra2018). Sensory imaginings can play a similar role given their similar format to episodic memory: one can imagine something and select aspects of one’s mental image to report.

I’ll now argue that when Oliver’s imagery plays this role in the production of his testimony, it’s because his imagery is the format in which he brings to mind his beliefs about the events he’s testifying about. He then shares these beliefs with Esther via testimony.

In order for one’s utterances to constitute genuine testimony about a particular event, one must be thinking about that event with one’s utterances causally connected in the right way to these thoughts. One could merely recite some words one has memorized and appear to be producing testimony about that event, but actually testifying about that event seems to require mentally representing it. In Oliver’s case, he does this by bringing to mind mental imagery where the content of this imagery causally determines the content of his testimony.

More specifically, though, when testimony is a means of sharing a belief about an event, it seems that a testifier’s utterances need to be causally connected to her belief: the testifier must bring her belief to mind and generate her testimony based on this belief. In other words, one’s belief must play the very functional role I just attributed to Oliver’s mental imagery in BAD KITTY. This suggests that Oliver’s mental imagery is the format of his occurrent beliefs about the events he’s describing.

So, when one perceived an event firsthand, one can bring to mind beliefs about it in the form of an episodic memory of the event. One can then share one’s beliefs by expressing the contents of that memory in testimony. Similarly, sensorily imagining can be a way to bring to mind beliefs about an event. As Oliver does, one can imaginatively “simulate” an event one didn’t witness firsthand in order to arrive at beliefs about it. One can then share one’s beliefs by reporting the contents of that imagining. In both memory and imagination cases, one’s imagery of an event is the format of one’s beliefs about that event.

5.b Imagery across testimonial transmission

So far, I’ve separately covered the roles imagery plays in the minds of the listener (section 3) and testifier (section 4.a). However, it’s not merely that imagery happens to occur on both sides of the knowledge-transmission process. Rather, there’s a more intimate relationship between both subjects’ imagery.

Consider how, as Esther imagines in response to Oliver’s descriptions, we’d expect Esther’s imagery to resemble Oliver’s imagery—i.e., the way Esther imagines the events described should resemble the way Oliver remembers and imagines them. The neuroscience of speech production and comprehension is consistent with this: brain imaging shows that the neural patterns underlying situation modelling in the listener’s mind typically mirror those underlying the testifier’s imagery (Hasson et al. Reference Hasson, Ghazanfar, Galantucci, Garrod and Keysers2012; Silbert et al. Reference Silbert, Honey, Simony, Poeppel and Hasson2014), while the degree of similarity correlates with the degree to which a listener comprehends and can later recall the contents of testimony (Stephens, Silbert, and Hasson Reference Stephens, Silbert and Hasson2010; Zadbood et al. Reference Zadbood, Chen, Leong, Norman and Hasson2017).

But what, precisely, does it mean to say that the listener’s imagery “resembles” the testifier’s? We can cash this out in terms of the content of each’s imagery, or the information contained in each’s imagery: if Oliver’s imagery represents the cat knocking over the vase, then Esther’s imagery resembles Oliver’s when it represents the same content (of course, we wouldn’t expect these images to perfectly resemble one another; I’ll gloss over this complication for now, returning to it momentarily). Since I’ve argued that the mental imagery in each subject’s mind is the format of their beliefs, this means that for a listener to form imagery that mirrors the testifier’s is for her to form a belief with the same content as the testifier’s belief.

So, in relevant imagery cases like BAD KITTY, testimonial belief transmission is a process in which the listener constructs imagery whose content mirrors the content of the testifier’s imagery. Furthermore, I already argued in section 4.b that a testifier’s utterances cause a listener to construct mental imagery in an automatic, noninferential way. With this in mind, we can see that there’s a tight causal relationship between the testifier’s and listener’s respective beliefs, which are connected via the testifier’s speech. As per section 5.a, the testifier’s belief that P in the form of an occurrent mental image causes the production of his utterances; these utterances then automatically cause the listener to form a belief, constructing a mental image whose content mirrors that of the testifier’s image.

Now, in BAD KITTY, it seems obvious that there would be many discrepancies in the specifics of each subjects’ mental images. It’s not as if they’d represent all the details of the scene the same way—exactly where the cat was on the table, the exact arrangements of the vase shards on the floor, etc. These discrepancies might seem to problematize my claim that the content of Esther’s imagery comes to mirror the content of Oliver’s. However, my account in the paper thus far can accommodate this with some slight refinements.

First, consider Esther. Notice that we wouldn’t expect her to believe all the very specific details of her mental imagery beyond those which correspond with the content of Oliver’s testimony. Esther might believe the more general contents of her imagery, such as that the cat jumped onto the table and knocked the vase onto the floor. However, if we asked her whether she’s imagining more fine-grained details accurately, we’d expect her to acknowledge that she isn’t, and that she’s withholding belief in those fine-grained contents. We can think of the contents of her imagery which she doesn’t believe as details that are merely imaginatively “filled in” to fill out the scene. So, it’s not strictly speaking true that Esther’s imagery is overall a single belief, which is how I’ve glossed things in the paper so far. Instead, her imagery is a mix of both belief and mere imagining.

While this might sound strange, it seems less so when we recognize that similar phenomena arise in other domains. For example, it’s a widespread fact that episodic memories are imaginatively filled in in various respects with only certain contents corresponding to past experiences (De Brigard Reference De Brigard2014). This doesn’t seem to prevent us from genuinely remembering the contents that are accurate (cf. Munro Reference Munro2021), which makes one’s mental image a mixture of remembering and imagining. Similarly, if one thinks that perception is a distinct mental state from hallucination, an experience that involves a hallucinated object in the foreground with a veridically perceived background seems to be a mixture of perception and hallucination. Since this sort of “mixture” of mental states can arise elsewhere, it’s not so strange to say that Esther’s imagery is a mix of belief and mere imagining.

Next, consider Oliver. We typically don’t remember all the fine-grained details of an event accurately since various details are imaginatively filled in (De Brigard Reference De Brigard2014). However, we also don’t typically believe those inaccurate, fine-grained details. Empirical study shows that subjects tend to generate memory-based testimony in ways that accommodate inaccuracies. When asked to describe a scene from memory, subjects tend to generate descriptions in a way that comes very close to optimizing accuracy; they do so by only reporting the particular details of a memory image in which they have high confidence, as well as by describing a scene at a high enough level of generality that their descriptions gloss over inaccuracies in precise details (Koriat and Goldsmith Reference Koriat and Goldsmith1996). It thus seems that testifiers like Oliver withhold belief in specific contents of their mental imagery. Thus, like Esther, Oliver’s imagery is a mix of belief and mere imagining.

Now, consider the relationship between Esther and Oliver’s imagery. The contents of Oliver’s utterances correspond only to contents of his imagery which he believes—for example, that the cat knocked over the vase. Furthermore, when Esther constructs her imagery, she forms beliefs in the contents that correspond to the contents of Oliver’s testimony rather than in the contents which are imaginatively filled in. Accordingly, the “resemblance” that’s necessary for belief transmission between Oliver and Esther is a matching between (a) the contents of Oliver’s imagery that he believes and expresses in testimony, and (b) the contents of Esther’s imagery which are directly caused by Oliver’s utterances.

5.c In favor of the other minds approach

My account in this section so far reveals that in the imagery cases on which I’m focused, there’s a tight causal relationship between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs. Furthermore, across section 3 and section 4, I argued that no causal intermediary between these beliefs is part of the basis of the listener’s belief. In this subsection, I now argue in favor of the other minds approach by arguing that the causal relationship between each subject’s beliefs has the characteristics of the basing relation. I’ll begin with some more general discussion of the basing relation, then situate my imagery cases in relation to this discussion.

A belief can be based on another mental state either inferentially or noninferentially. Perceptual beliefs are often thought to be noninferential: one has a perceptual experience as of P, and this noninferentially causes one to believe that P (e.g., Pryor Reference Pryor2000; Huemer Reference Huemer2006). It’s also often thought that introspection is noninferential: that mere introspective awareness of one’s own mental states serves as the noninferential basis for beliefs about one’s mental states (e.g., Armstrong Reference Armstrong and Cassam1994). It’s controversial whether perception and introspection are indeed noninferential, but I’ll assume they are in what follows. (This is merely so I have some illustrative examples of noninferential beliefs so readers who disagree can substitute their favorite examples.)

A paradigmatic case of inferential basing is forming the belief that Q on the basis of one’s belief that P and one’s belief that if P, then Q. As in this example, the contents of inferential beliefs are typically distinct from the contents of the bases on which they’re formed. (Perhaps one could also infer that P from a belief that P; my point is just that it’s a widespread feature of inferential beliefs that their contents are distinct from the contents of their bases.)

In contrast, as long as nothing has gone epistemically awry, the content of noninferential beliefs matches the content of the mental states on which they’re based. In perception, one typically forms the belief that P because the content of one’s belief is causally sensitive to the content of one’s experience as of P. However, when one has an experience as of P but forms the belief that Q—for example, if an experience as of a tomato on the table causes the belief that there’s a watermelon on the table—this is because something has gone wrong. It could be, for example, that some psychological malfunction causes one’s perceptual belief-forming system not to be properly sensitive to one’s experience, or that one just wasn’t properly paying attention to one’s experience.Footnote 15

Similarly, in introspection, one typically forms the belief that one possesses mental state M because the content of one’s belief is causally sensitive to the content of one’s introspective awareness as of M. When one has an introspective awareness as of M but forms the belief that one possesses mental state N, this is because something has gone wrong. It could again be that some psychological malfunction has occurred in one’s belief-forming process, or one could be somehow misled—for example, if a therapist one takes to be reliable has misled one to think an introspective awareness as of anxiety is caused by indigestion.

So, sensitivity of the content of a belief to the content of its base such that the two end up matching is a hallmark of noninferential basing. Unlike inferential cases, the two only fail to match when things go wrong epistemically.

Now, my arguments above in section 4.b show that imagery cases of testimonial transmission are noninferential. In that subsection, I appealed to empirical evidence to argue that hearing a testifier’s speech causes a listener to construct mental imagery in a noninferential way. So, if the listener’s testimonial belief is based on the testifier’s belief, we should expect the causal relationship that holds between their imagery to be structurally like the relationship between base and belief in paradigmatic examples of noninferential belief, such as perception and introspection. In other words, we’d expect that the content of the listener’s belief is causally sensitive to the content of the testifier’s belief such that the two end up matching, unless something goes wrong. I’ll now argue that the relationship between the two beliefs does exhibit these properties.

First, consider when everything goes well in the belief transmission process, as described in section 5.b. In relevant cases, testimonial transmission is a process in which the testifier’s imagery causes his speech, which then directly causes the listener to construct imagery whose content recapitulates the content of the testifier’s imagery. In these cases, each subject’s imagery is their belief. So, when everything goes well and a belief that P is successfully transmitted from testifier to listener, the listener forms a belief with content P because the content of her belief is causally sensitive to the content of the testifier’s belief. This looks much like the relationship between base and belief in perception and introspection.

Furthermore, the content of the listener’s belief only fails to match the content of the testifier’s belief when things go wrong. This could be because of a failure on the part of the listener, as in this case:

MISHEARING ESTHER: Oliver tells Esther, “The cat broke the vase.” Esther is only half paying attention to Oliver, and she mishears him as saying, “Matt broke the vase.” She therefore forms the belief that their son Matt broke the vase.

A lack of sensitivity of the content of Esther’s belief to Oliver’s could also stem from a failure of Oliver to successfully transmit his belief:

MISSPEAKING OLIVER: Oliver intends to tell Esther that the cat broke the vase. However, he accidentally misspeaks and says, “Matt broke the vase,” causing Esther to form the belief that Matt broke the vase.

Both these kinds of cases involve a failure in the testimonial transmission process, the result being that the content of Esther’s belief fails to be causally sensitive to the content of Oliver’s belief. Barring such malfunctions in the transmission process, this sensitivity obtains. This again makes the relation between beliefs much like the relations in other cases of noninferential belief.

So, in imagery cases of testimonial transmission like BAD KITTY, the causal relationship between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs has the properties of paradigmatic cases of noninferential basing. The content of the listener’s testimonial belief is causally sensitive to the content of the testifier’s belief such that the listener forms a belief whose content matches that of the testifier’s. And, when this matching fails to occur, it’s because something has gone wrong (unlike cases of inferential belief, where the contents of beliefs are typically distinct from the contents of their bases, and where this doesn’t necessarily mean anything has gone wrong).

This gives us inductive support for the hypothesis that the listener’s belief is based on the testifier’s belief, which in turn supports the other minds approach. Because the listener’s belief is noninferential in relevant imagery cases, this hypothesis predicts that the relationship between each subject’s beliefs exhibits the characteristic properties of noninferential basing. As I just argued, this prediction is confirmed both in cases where belief transmission goes well and in cases where it malfunctions.

The other minds approach thus gives a plausible account of imagery cases of testimonial transmission. Furthermore, sections 34 have already argued that no causal intermediary between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs is included in the listener’s basis. So, given the absence of a plausible alternative view, we should accept the other minds approach. Thus, in at least some cases, the basis of the listener’s testimonial belief that P is the testifier’s belief that P.Footnote 16

6. Intentionally misleading testimony and the epistemological significance of the other minds approach

To motivate the other minds approach, I argued that the testifier’s belief can be the basis of a listener’s belief. But what about cases where there’s no testifier’s belief to serve as the listener’s basis because the testifier is transmitting information which she doesn’t believe? In this section, I extend the other minds approach to such cases. In doing so, I bring out the epistemological significance of replacing the standard internalist approach with the other minds approach.

Notice that even when the testifier doesn’t believe the content of her own testimony, there can still be a causal relationship between representations in the minds of the testifier and listener. Consider:

LYING OLIVER: Esther asks Oliver what happened to the broken vase. In reality, Oliver had knocked the vase off the table by accident. Ashamed to admit this, he quickly tries to imagine another scenario to explain why the vase is broken. He then reports the scenario he just invented in his imagination: “The cat jumped onto the table and knocked the vase to the floor.” Esther trusts Oliver and accepts what he says.

Suppose Esther imagines what Oliver describes as a way of simultaneously comprehending his testimony and forming a testimonial belief, much as in BAD KITTY.

Even though Esther’s belief is false, a causal relationship would hold between each subject’s mental imagery that’s similar to the one in BAD KITTY: Oliver has imagined a scenario, the content of his mental imagery causally determines the content of his utterances, and these utterances cause Esther to construct mental imagery of the scene Oliver describes. So, for all the same reasons that I argued Esther’s imagery was based on Oliver’s in BAD KITTY, Esther’s imagery is based on Oliver’s in this case. The difference is that in LYING OLIVER, Esther’s belief is based on what is merely an imagining in Oliver’s mind, while in BAD KITTY her belief is based on an imagining which is a belief.

Comparing LYING OLIVER and BAD KITTY suggests one way in which the other minds approach and the standard internalist approach differ in terms of which beliefs they count as justified. Assume that in these cases, Esther has all the same internal mental states: her experience of Oliver’s testimony, her belief about what Oliver said, and the like. The standard internalist approach would then count Esther’s belief as equally justified in each of these cases given the internalist commitment that only a subject’s own mental states count as reasons for her beliefs.

However, the other minds approach would plausibly say Esther’s belief has a greater degree of justification in BAD KITTY than in LYING OLIVER. In BAD KITTY, her belief is based on Oliver’s belief. In general, a competent, trustworthy testifier’s belief that P seems like a good reason to believe P since what a fellow rational subject believes is typically a good guide to the truth. In contrast, Esther’s belief in LYING OLIVER is based on a mere imagining. While I’ve argued that some imaginings count as beliefs, Oliver’s in LYING OLIVER does not. In general, another subject’s mere imagining doesn’t seem like a good reason to form a belief since people imagine things all the time that aren’t true.

It therefore seems that on the other minds approach, Esther has a good reason for her belief in BAD KITTY which she doesn’t possess in LYING OLIVER. So, replacing the standard internalist approach with the other minds approach seems to have consequences for how we evaluate the epistemic status of testimonial beliefs.

7. Extending the other minds approach to nonimagery cases?

I’ve focused on a certain kind of imagery case, and my arguments have relied directly on the psychological roles imagery plays in such cases. Section 3 relied on the fact that the same instance of mental imagery can serve both comprehension and belief formation, building on this to argue, against the standard internalist approach, that the two can occur simultaneously. In arguing against various alternatives to the standard internalist approach, section 4 relied again on this claim about simultaneity, as well as on evidence that a testifier’s speech causes imagery in an automatic, noninferential way. Finally, section 5 relied in part on this same point about the noninferentiality of imagistic beliefs, arguing that the relationship between the testifier’s and listener’s beliefs is a basing relationship.

Imagery’s role in language comprehension has been studied in depth, making imagery cases especially amenable to my empirically informed arguments. However, it seems many cases of testimonial transmission don’t involve mental imagery. If I tell you, for example, that Descartes authored the Meditations, or that hydrogen’s atomic number is 1, it doesn’t seem like either my sharing or you acquiring these beliefs need involve mental imagery. Instead, such cases may involve representations with a discursive or linguistic format. It’s therefore worth asking whether my arguments for the other minds approach could be extended to such nonimagery cases. I’ll now sketch how such an extension might go while noting where more evidence is needed to decide if it’s successful.

Consider a more abstract description of the process involved in imagery cases, but one which doesn’t mention imagery. A testifier first brings to mind a belief she wishes to share with a listener; then, the content of the representation before the testifier’s mind causally determines the content of her utterances; finally, these utterances noninferentially cause the listener to form a representation with the same content as the listener’s belief, by which she simultaneously comprehends the listener’s utterance and forms a testimonial belief.

It’s possible that this same abstract structure could describe at least some nonimagery cases. If comprehension and belief formation can occur simultaneously in the listener’s mind in nonimagery cases, then section 3’s arguments against the standard internalist approach to such cases would apply. Furthermore, if the listener’s belief can be formed noninferentially, then section 4’s arguments against alternatives to the standard internalist approach would also apply. And, if the listener’s belief is noninferential, then it could be causally sensitive to the testifier’s belief in the way that’s necessary for section 5’s arguments in favor of other minds approach.

All of this depends in part on some empirical questions. For example, it’s an empirical question whether comprehension and belief formation can occur simultaneously in nonimagery cases. One reason to think this is possible is that situation modelling processes similar to those operative in imagery cases have been used by some empirical researchers to describe nonimagery cases. Kintsch (Reference Kintsch1988), for example, describes the perception of speech as activating a purely propositional constructive process. This involves the activation of nodes in an associative network where concepts and associations between them are activated to construct representations (e.g., concepts for Descartes, Meditations, and authored). It’s possible that, as in the case of constructing mental imagery, such situation modelling could simultaneously be a process of comprehension and belief formation.

It’s less clear whether empirical evidence supports the idea that nonimagistic testimonial beliefs can be formed noninferentially in response to a testifier’s speech. My argument in the case of imagistic beliefs depended on the way speech automatically modulates perceptual processing, including low-level perceptual areas that are outside the remit of person-level inference. Since it relies on findings specifically about imagery, this argument can’t simply be extended to nonimagistic situation models that are propositional in format. We’d therefore need some other kind of evidence.

For all I’ve said, we don’t have reason to deny that my arguments could extend to some nonimagistic cases. However, more work needs to be done to settle this.

8. Conclusion

I opened section 1 by noting the striking fact that during testimonial transmission, a listener often constructs mental imagery that resembles imagery before the testifier’s mind. This parallel between the way each subject represents the world seemed to cry out for an explanation, and I’ve argued that mental imagery often plays fundamental roles in the psychology of testimonial transmission. In cases like this, a listener’s imagery can be intimately causally linked to the testifier’s imagery.

Such cases pose a problem for the standard internalist approach to conceptualizing the basis of testimonial beliefs, on which a listener’s basis is always one of the listener’s own mental states. Based on the relationship between each subject’s imagery, I argued that a listener’s testimonial belief can instead be based on a testifier’s belief. I therefore concluded that the basis of a testimonial belief can be external to the listener’s mind.

Acknowledgments

For comments and discussion on this material, thank you to David Barnett, Tim Kenyon, Liang Zhou Koh, Kourken Michaelian, Jennifer Nagel, Gurpreet Rattan, Luke Roelofs, Stephanie Sheintul, Zach Weinstein, two anonymous reviewers for this journal, and audiences at the Canadian Philosophical Association, Waterloo Graduate Philosophy Conference, Western Canadian Philosophical Association, American Philosophical Association, and Bochum-Grenoble Memory Colloquium. Thank you also to the editors of The Junkyard blog where early versions of these ideas appeared. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Daniel Munro is a postdoctoral fellow in philosophy at the University of Toronto. His main research interests concern the nature and epistemic significance of the imagination, as well as the relationships between imagination, memory, and perception.

Footnotes

1 For simplicity, I’ll continue to write about testimony in terms of a listener hearing a testifier’s speech. But my arguments should apply to other ways of receiving testimony (e.g., via text, sign languages).

2 A further complication: while it seems intuitive to say Esther’s imagery would “resemble” Oliver’s, it’s not clear exactly what this means. I return to this below.

3 Since this causal view features heavily in my arguments, it’s worth briefly sketching some support for it, though a detailed defense is beyond my scope. Turri (Reference Turri2011) defends it based on the fact that reasons for beliefs are difference-makers. Suppose you initially think S believes P based on some factor Φ. However, you then find out that Φ actually made no difference whatsoever to whether S believed P. Consequently, you’d likely no longer think S’s belief was based on Φ. Turri argues that since it’s intuitive to equate difference-makers with causes, this suggests bases of beliefs are causes.

4 I’ve argued that various epistemologists take the basis of testimonial beliefs to include a mental state representing the content of the testifier’s utterance. But are they really all full-blooded internalists about testimony—i.e., they include no factors in a listener’s basis which are external to her mind? Their full accounts of the listener’s basis suggest they are. Malmgren (Reference Malmgren2006, sec. 8) unpacks the listener’s basis in terms of an inference from other beliefs; Barnett (Reference Barnett2015) explicitly claims the listener’s justification depends solely on “internal” factors (357); Fricker (Reference Fricker1987) discusses justification in terms of an ability to reconstruct a chain of doxastic or subdoxastic causes of a belief; and Longworth (Reference Longworth2018) argues comprehension “immediately” justifies testimonial beliefs, language epistemologists typically use to mean one’s justification doesn’t depend on any other premises or beliefs.

5 Strictly speaking, the authors I cited don’t explicitly claim this is the only way to form justified testimonial beliefs, rather than merely one way among others. However, since their stated goal in the cited works is to give an account of the epistemology of testimony, and since they don’t describe alternative belief-forming processes, I assume they take the process they describe to be distinctive of properly testimonial beliefs.

6 An anonymous reviewer suggests that the other minds approach may have undesirable consequences if the basing relation is transitive. Suppose the listener’s testimonial belief that P is based on the testifier’s belief that P, and that the testifier’s belief is based on (e.g.) a past experience of P. If basing is transitive, then the listener’s testimonial belief is also based on the testifier’s past experience, which might seem counterintuitive. It’s controversial whether basing is transitive. However, I’m happy to bite the bullet and grant to anyone who accepts this that the other minds view simply has a counterintuitive consequence: that the listener’s basis includes the testifier’s past experience. Furthermore, such a view isn’t unheard of: at least one recent account of basing by a prominent externalist, Nagel (Reference Nagel, Brown and Simion2021), agrees that the listener’s basis extends back through the testifier’s experience.

7 To further clarify the dialectic of this section: my accounts of imagery’s role in comprehension (section 3.a) and belief-formation (section 3.b) will on their own be consistent with certain versions of the standard internalist approach. My arguments against this approach come in section 3.d and depend on the full picture developed across sections 3.a3.c, rather than on any part of this picture in isolation.

8 Werning (Reference Werning2020) considers similar phenomena in developing his notion of “vicarious experiences,” which occur when testimony generates “a rich, ‘as if you were there’ experience in the listener due to the vividness, detailedness, concreteness, intensity and emotionality of the linguistically conveyed content” (324). The kind of cases I’m considering include such ‘vicarious experiences.’ However, I don’t restrict my focus to cases of recreating the speaker’s experience in vivid detail. In BAD KITTY, Esther might imagine the cat knocking over the vase without vividly recreating what it was like for Oliver to experience this: she might not recreate various details like the emotions Oliver felt, the way he acted in response to the cat knocking over the vase, etc.

9 Situation models involve mental imagery in the same way episodic memory and other kinds of imagination involve imagery. Recent philosophical and empirical work has converged on the idea that images involved in remembering and imagining are constructed by combining details from past experiences (e.g., representations of objects one experienced in the past), guided by more abstract representations (e.g., background beliefs about the world, abstract “schemas” for general event types) (Michaelian Reference Michaelian2016; Addis Reference Addis2018). Work on situation modeling describes it similarly, as a constructive process that draws on various types of stored information and knowledge.

10 Strictly speaking, the evidence I described for this view is consistent with thinking that we form and store both a situation model and a distinct belief. However, given that the situation model already plays the functional role of a belief, it would be psychologically redundant to posit two, distinct representations playing this same role. In general, we should avoid theories that posit redundant entities when a simpler theory would do just as well.

11 An anonymous reviewer objects that my argument in this subsection relies on an overly simplistic understanding of memory storage and retrieval. Recent empirical work reveals that when we perceive or imagine something, we don’t simply store an overall copy of that percept or image, much as one might snap a photo then file it away for later retrieval. Instead, perceiving and imagining cause us to store representations of particular event details (objects, people, places, etc.), as well as form or strengthen associations between details. Retrieval is then a process of reconstructing a prior experience or image by activating event details and associations between them, in a way that’s guided by more abstract beliefs, schemas for general event types, and the like (see Footnote footnote 9 above). It might seem that when I say we construct a situation model then commit it to memory for later retrieval, I’m assuming the naïve “snapshot” view of imagistic representations. However, I think this objection relies on an overly simplistic view of the nature of belief storage and retrieval. On my account, constructing a situation model is a process of forming an occurrent testimonial belief. However, subsequently committing this belief to memory, making it available for later retrieval, needn’t involve storing a replica of the image one initially constructed. Various philosophers argue that we can possess implicit beliefs (e.g., Gertler Reference Gertler and Hatzimoysis2011), and implicit representations more generally (e.g., Dennett Reference Dennett1982), whose contents depend on their interrelations with other explicit representations. If the process of memory encoding stores enough explicit information that it produces a relatively stable disposition to, upon retrieval, reconstruct a prior conscious situation model, then I see no reason to deny that one has (implicitly) committed that situation model to memory. For related discussion about episodic memory, see Munro (Reference Munro2021).

12 It’s beyond my scope to offer a detailed defense of Nguyen’s account, but I’ll sketch two considerations. First, as Nguyen argues, it seems his account accurately captures one central, paradigmatic instance of trust: children’s trust in their caregivers. It seems doubtful that young children typically deliberate or form conscious attitudes before trusting their caregivers—instead, under normal circumstances they’re simply disposed to take them at face value. Second, Nguyen’s account has some support from neuroscientific research on trust: Schjoedt et al. (Reference Schjoedt, Sørensen, Nielbo, Xygalatas, Mitkidis and Bulbulia2013) argue, based in part on neuroscientific study of trust in charismatic religious authorities, that trust involves the brain inhibiting executive functioning and error monitoring such that listeners simply passively rely on trusted subjects.

13 After all, BAD KITTY is a mundane, straightforward case of testimonial belief formation with nothing epistemically suspect going on: Esther simply trusts her spouse, Oliver, so takes what he says at face value. Unless we want to be skeptics about much of our everyday testimonial belief formation, it seems we should consider Esther justified.

14 Burge’s full account of testimonial justification is complex, and I don’t mean to endorse his entire picture (see Malmgren Reference Malmgren2006 for detailed discussion). Rather, I just endorse this specific claim about the relation between perceiving speech and comprehending it.

15 An anonymous reviewer presses the following worry. Suppose I have an experience of P&Q, and, on this basis, I form the belief that P. It seems plausible that this belief could be noninferentially based on my experience of P&Q, while nothing has gone wrong in my belief formation. That would mean a belief that P could be noninferentially based on a state with distinct content P&Q rather than its content matching its base. In response, note that any experience which is accurately described as an experience of P&Q can also be accurately described as an experience of P. If I simultaneously experience a tomato on the table and an apple on the table, my experience can also accurately be described as either “an experience of a tomato on the table” or “an experience of an apple on the table” (hence, I could truthfully assert either “I see a tomato on the table” or “I see an apple on the table”). Similarly, an experience representing John as tall and thin is also accurately described as either representing John as tall or representing John as thin. Thus, any experience of P&Q is also an experience of P. So, any belief that P based on an experience of P&Q is based on an experience of P.

16 Instead of the other minds approach, an alternative might be to argue (following Clark and Chalmers’ (Reference Clark and Chalmers1998) “extended mind” thesis) that the testifier’s belief can literally be a belief of the listener’s, much as Clark and Chalmers argue entries in a notebook can be a listener’s memories. To evaluate this, we’d have to explore whether the testifier’s belief plays a functional role for the listener, which is equivalent, in relevant respects, to the functional role of the listener’s internal beliefs. While this is a very interesting line of inquiry, it’s one I don’t have space to explore here, though I hope to do so in future work. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting it.

References

Addis, Donna Rose. 2018. “Are Episodic Memories Special? On the Sameness of Remembered and Imagined Event Simulation.” Journal of the Royal Society of New Zealand 48 (2–3): 6488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1994. “Introspection.” In Self-Knowledge, edited by Cassam, Quassim, 109117. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnett, David James. 2015. “Is Memory Merely Testimony from One’s Former Self?Philosophical Review 124 (3): 353–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boutonnet, Bastien, and Lupyan, Gary. 2015. “Words Jump-Start Vision: A Label Advantage in Object Recognition.” The Journal of Neuroscience 35 (25): 9329–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bransford, John D., Barclay, J. Richard, and Franks, Jeffery J.. 1972. “Sentence Memory: A Constructive versus Interpretive Approach.” Cognitive Psychology 3 (2): 193209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brogaard, Berit. 2018. “In Defense of Hearing Meanings.” Synthese 195 (7): 2967–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1993. “Content Preservation.” The Philosophical Review 102 (4): 457–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Alex. 2009. “Experience and Content.” The Philosophical Quarterly 59 (236): 429–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Alex. 2010. “Recollection, Perception, Imagination.” Philosophical Studies 148 (1): 1526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, David, and Kornblith, Hilary. 1997. “Testimony, Memory and the Limits of the a Priori.” Philosophical Studies 86 (1): 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy. 2016. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy, and Chalmers, David. 1998. “The Extended Mind.” Analysis 58 (1): 719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Brigard, Felipe. 2014. “Is Memory for Remembering? Recollection as a Form of Episodic Hypothetical Thinking.” Synthese 191 (2): 155–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1982. “Styles of Mental Representation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83: 213–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1997. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, Richard, and Conee, Earl. 2001. “Internalism Defended.” American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (1): 118.Google Scholar
Fernández, Jordi. 2006. “The Intentionality of Memory.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (1): 3957.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fincher-Kiefer, Rebecca. 2001. “Perceptual Components of Situation Models.” Memory & Cognition 29 (2): 336–43.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fricker, Elizabeth. 1987. “The Epistemology of Testimony.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 61 (supp. vol.): 5783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth. 2003. “Understanding and Knowledge of What Is Said.” In Epistemology of Language, edited by Barber, Alex, 325–66. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gertler, Brie. 2011. “Self-Knowledge and the Transparency of Belief.” In Self-Knowledge, edited by Hatzimoysis, Anthony, 125–45. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glenberg, Arthur M., Meyer, Marion, and Lindem, Karen. 1987. “Mental Models Contribute to Foregrounding during Text Comprehension.” Journal of Memory and Language 26 (1): 6983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasson, Uri, Ghazanfar, Asif A., Galantucci, Bruno, Garrod, Simon, and Keysers, Christian. 2012. “Brain-to-Brain Coupling: A Mechanism for Creating and Sharing a Social World.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (2): 114–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huemer, Michael. 2006. “Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition.” American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (2): 147–58.Google Scholar
Jones, Max, and Wilkinson, Sam. 2020. “From Prediction to Imagination.” In The Cambridge Handbook of the Imagination, edited by Abraham, Anna, 94110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1968. “Quantifying In.” Synthese 19 (1): 178214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kintsch, Walter. 1988. “The Role of Knowledge in Discourse Comprehension: A Construction-Integration Model.” Psychological Review 95 (2): 163.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Korez, Keith Allen. 1997. “Recent Work on the Basing Relation.” American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (2): 171–91.Google Scholar
Koriat, Asher, and Goldsmith, Morris. 1996. “Memory Metaphors and the Real-Life/Laboratory Controversy: Correspondence versus Storehouse Conceptions of Memory.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2): 167–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurby, Christopher A., and Zacks, Jeffrey M.. 2013. “The Activation of Modality-Specific Representations during Discourse Processing.” Brain and Language 126 (3): 338–49.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Langland-Hassan, Peter. 2020. Explaining Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longworth, Guy. 2018. “Understanding What Was Said.” Synthese 195 (2): 815–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lupyan, Gary, and Clark, Andy. 2015. “Words and the World: Predictive Coding and the Language-Perception-Cognition Interface.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 24 (4): 279–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahr, Johannes, and Csibra, Gergely. 2018. “Why Do We Remember? The Communicative Function of Episodic Memory.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19: 193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malmgren, Anna-Sara. 2006. “Is There a Priori Knowledge by Testimony?The Philosophical Review 115 (2): 199241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mar, Raymond A. 2004. “The Neuropsychology of Narrative: Story Comprehension, Story Production and Their Interrelation.” Neuropsychologia 42 (10): 1414–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McClelland, James L., Hill, Felix, Rudolph, Maja, Baldridge, Jason, and Schütze, Hinrich. 2019. “Extending Machine Language Models toward Human-Level Language Understanding.” arXiv:1912.05877.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 1994. “Knowledge by Hearsay.” In Knowing from Words: Western and Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, edited by Matilal, Bimal Krishna and Chakrabarti, Arindam, 195224. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michaelian, Kourken. 2016. Mental Time Travel: Episodic Memory and Our Knowledge of the Personal Past. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munro, Daniel. 2021. “Remembering the Past and Imagining the Actual.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 12: 175–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Jennifer. 2021. “Losing Knowledge by Thinking about Thinking.” In Reasons, Justification and Defeat, edited by Brown, Jessica and Simion, Mona, 6992. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nanay, Bence. 2021. “Mental Imagery.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter), edited by Zalta, Edward N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-imagery/.Google Scholar
Nanay, Bence. 2015. “Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery.” Philosophical Studies 172 (7): 1723–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, C. Thi. Forthcoming. “Trust as an Unquestioning Attitude.” Oxford Studies in Epistemology.Google Scholar
Pearson, Joel, and Kosslyn, Stephen M.. 2015. “The Heterogeneity of Mental Representation: Ending the Imagery Debate.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 112 (33): 10089–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pryor, James. 2000. “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.” Noûs 34 (4): 517–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schjoedt, Uffe, Sørensen, Jesper, Nielbo, Kristoffer Laigaard, Xygalatas, Dimitris, Mitkidis, Panagiotis, and Bulbulia, Joseph. 2013. “Cognitive Resource Depletion in Religious Interactions.” Religion, Brain and Behavior 3 (1): 3955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silbert, Lauren J., Honey, Christopher J., Simony, Erez, Poeppel, David, and Hasson, Uri. 2014. “Coupled Neural Systems Underlie the Production and Comprehension of Naturalistic Narrative Speech.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 111 (43): E4687–96.Google ScholarPubMed
Stephens, Greg J., Silbert, Lauren J., and Hasson, Uru. 2010. “Speaker-Listener Neural Coupling Underlies Successful Communication.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 107 (32): 14425–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sylvan, Kurt. 2016. “Epistemic Reasons II: Basing.” Philosophy Compass 11 (7): 377–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John. 2011. “Believing for a Reason.” Erkenntnis 74 (3): 383–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Leeuwen, Neil. 2013. “The Meanings of “imagine” Part I: Constructive Imagination.” Philosophy Compass 8 (3): 220–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph. 2002. “Internalism Explained.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2): 349–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Werning, Markus. 2020. “Predicting the Past from Minimal Traces: Episodic Memory and its Distinction from Imagination and Preservation.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 11 (2): 301–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westra, Evan, and Nagel, Jennifer. 2021. “Mindreading in Conversation.” Cognition 210: 104618.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, Roger. 2014. “What Is My Evidence That Here Is a Hand?” In Scepticism and Perceptual Justification, edited by Dodd, Dylan and Zardini, Ella, 298321. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zacks, Jeffrey M., Mar, Raymond A., and Calarco, Navona. 2018. “The Cognitive Neuroscience of Discourse: Covered Ground and New Directions.” In The Routledge Handbook of Discourse Processes, edited by Schober, Michael F., Rapp, David N., and Britt, Anne M., 269–94. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Zadbood, Asieh, Chen, Janice, Leong, Yuan Chang, Norman, Kenneth A., and Hasson, Uri. 2017. “How We Transmit Memories to Other Brains: Constructing Shared Neural Representations Via Communication.” Cerebral Cortex 27 (10): 49885000.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zwaan, Rolf A. 2016. “Situation Models, Mental Simulations, and Abstract Concepts in Discourse Comprehension.” Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 23 (4): 1028–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zwaan, Rolf A., and Radvansky, Gabriel A.. 1998. “Situation Models in Language Comprehension and Memory.” Psychological Bulletin 123 (2): 162.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed