Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T13:10:36.842Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral Enhancement and Moral Freedom: A Critique of the Little Alex Problem

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 October 2018

John Danaher*
Affiliation:
National University of Ireland, Galway

Abstract

A common objection to moral enhancement is that it would undermine our moral freedom and that this is a bad thing because moral freedom is a great good. Michael Hauskeller has defended this view on a couple of occasions using an arresting thought experiment called the “Little Alex” problem. In this chapter, I reconstruct the argument Hauskeller derives from this thought experiment and subject it to critical scrutiny. I claim that the argument ultimately fails because (a) it assumes that moral freedom is an intrinsic good when, in fact, it is more likely to be an axiological catalyst; and (b) there are reasons to think that moral enhancement does not undermine moral freedom.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Persson, I. and Savulescu, J., Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Harris, J., ‘Moral Enhancement and Freedom’, Bioethics 25:2 (2011), 102111CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

3 Harris, , How to Be Good: The Possibility of Moral Enhancement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Harris, J., ‘Moral Blindness – The Gift of the God Machine9:3 (2016), 269273Google Scholar; Persson, I. and Savulescu, J., ‘Enharrisment: A Reply to John Harris about Moral Enhancement’, Neuroethics 9:3 (2016), 275–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Persson, I. and Savulescu, J., ‘Moral Bioenhancement, Freedom and Reason’, Neuroethics 9:3 (2016), 263268CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

4 Sparrow, R., ‘Better Living Through Chemistry? A Reply to Savulescu and Persson on “Moral Enhancement”’, Journal of Applied Philosophy 31:1 (2014), 2332CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Hauskeller, M., ‘The “Little Alex” Problem’, The Philosophers’ Magazine 62 (2013), 7478CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Hauskeller, M., ‘Is it Desirable to Be Able to Do the Undesirable? Moral Bioenhancement and the Little Alex Problem’, Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26:3 (2017), 365376CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 de Melo-Martín, I. and Salles, A., ‘Moral Bioenhancement: Much Ado About Nothing?’, Bioethics 29:4 (2014), 223232, 224CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Buchanan, A., Beyond Humanity? The Ethics of Biomedical Enhancement (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 See, for example, Harris, J., Enhancing Evolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007)Google Scholar and Buchanan, Beyond Humanity.

9 List, C. and Vallentini, L., ‘Freedom as Independence’, Ethics 126:4 (2016), 10431074CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Hauskeller, ‘The “Little Alex” Problem’, 75.

11 On the different problems of evil, see Mackie, J. L., ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, Mind 64:254 (1955), 200212CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Plantinga, A., God, Freedom and Evil (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1977)Google Scholar; and Rowe, W., ‘The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism’, American Philosophical Association 16:4 (1979), 335341Google Scholar.

12 For example Bergmann, M., ‘Skeptical Theism and Rowe's New Evidential Argument from Evil’, Nous 35:2 (2001), 278296CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Plantinga, God, Freedom and Evil.

14 Swinburne, R., The Existence of God, 2nd edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Pereboom, D., ‘Free Will, Evil and Divine Providence’, in Dole, A. and Chignell, A. (eds), God and the Ethics of Belief (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 7798CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Maitzen, S., ‘Ordinary Morality Implies Atheism’, European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 1:2 (2009), 107126CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Kane, R., The Significance of Free Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar.

18 Balaguer, M., Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010)Google Scholar.

19 Dworkin, G., The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fischer, J. M. and Ravizza, M., Responsibility and Control (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Frankfurt, H., ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, Journal of Philosophy 68:1 (1971), 520CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Maslen, H., Pugh, J., and Savulescu, J., ‘The Ethics of Deep Brain Stimulation for Anorexia Nervosa’, Neuroethics 8:3 (2015), 215230CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Gaus, G., The Order of Public Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Pettit, P., Just Freedom (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 2014)Google Scholar.

22 Though see Sparrow, ‘Better Living Through Chemistry?’.

23 Hauskeller, ‘The “Little Alex” Problem’, 78–79.

24 Hauskeller, ‘The “Little Alex” Problem’, 79.

25 Petersen, S., ‘Designing People to Serve’, in Lin, P., Abney, G., and Bekey, K. (eds), Robot Ethics: The Ethical and Social Implications of Robotics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2012), 283298Google Scholar.