Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-01T12:18:24.624Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Importance, Fame, and Death

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 November 2021

Guy Kahane*
Affiliation:
University of Oxford

Abstract

Some people want their lives to possess importance on a large scale. Some crave fame, or at least wide recognition. And some even desire glory that will only be realised after their death. Such desires are either ignored or disparaged by many philosophers. However, although few of us have a real shot at importance and fame on any grand scale, these can be genuine personal goods when they meet certain further conditions. Importance that relates to positive impact and reflects our agency answers a distinctive existential concern for one's life to matter. And since what is important merits wide appreciation, the step from wanting to be significant and wanting that significance widely appreciated is small. Still, desires for importance and fame can take a more vicious character when they are not properly structured, and when they are not dominated by more impartial aims. If we accept the personal value of importance and fame, it is hard to see why that value cannot extend beyond our death. The temporal distribution of glory is actually irrelevant to its value. But it is also a mistake to identify a concern with posthumous glory with the wish to leave a trace after our death.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, Woody, The Illustrated Woody Allen Reader (New York: Random House, 1995).Google Scholar
Amis, Martin, ‘Career Move’, in his Heavy Water and Other Stories (London: Jonathan Cape, 1998).Google Scholar
Benatar, David, The Human Predicament (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. Watts, V.E., (London: Penguin Books, 1969).Google Scholar
Campbell, Stephen M. and Nyholm, Sven, ‘Anti-meaning and why it matters’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (2015), 694711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canetti, Elias, Crowds and Power, (New York: Viking Press, 1962).Google Scholar
Chappell, Timothy, ‘Glory as an Ethical Idea’, Philosophical Investigations 34 (2011), 105134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Confucius, The Analects of Confucius, translated by Legge, J., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1861).Google Scholar
Wallace, David Foster, ‘Good Old Neon’, in his Oblivion: Stories (New York: Little, Brown, and Co, 2014).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, ‘The Usefulness of Finals Ends’, in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Gauss, Christian, ‘Prophecies by Stendhal’, Modern Language Notes 38 (1923).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halberstam, Joshua, ‘Fame’, American Philosophical Quarterly 21 (1984), 9399.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas, Virtue, Vice and Value (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Johnson, Samuel, The Rambler (1751).Google Scholar
Kahane, Guy, ‘Our Cosmic Insignificance’, Noûs 48 (2014), 745–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, Guy, ‘Importance, Value, and Causal Impact’, The Journal of Moral Philosophy (2021, forthcoming a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, Guy, ‘The Significance of the Past’, The Journal of the American Philosophical Association (2021, forthcoming b).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, Guy, ‘Meaningfulness and Importance’, in Landau, Iddo (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Meaning in Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).Google Scholar
Kauppinen, Antti, ‘Meaningfulness and Time’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84 (2012), 345–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard, What is Good and Why (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Douglas, ‘Fame as a Value Concept’, Philosophy Research Archives 12 (1986), 541–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margalit, Avishai, The Ethics of Memory (Harvard: Harvard University Press. 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metz, Thaddeus, Meaning in Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muhlstein, Anka, ‘Degas Invents a New World’, The New York Review, (12 May 2016).Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, What Does It All Mean? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, ‘Importance’, in The Examined Life (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1989).Google Scholar
Plutarch, Moralia, XIV (Cambridge, MA: Loeb Classical Library, 1967).Google Scholar
Roskam, Geert, Live Unnoticed: On the Vissicitudes of an Epicurean Doctrine (Leiden: Brill, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Maxwell, ‘Stendhal, Hyphen-Mark in the History of French Fiction’, The French Review 16 (1942).Google Scholar
Strawson, Galen, ‘Blood and Memory’, The Guardian, (4 January 2003).Google Scholar
Temkin, Larry, ‘Rationality with Respect to People, Places, and Times’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (2015), 576608.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Unamuno, Miguel, The Tragic Sense of Life (London: Macmillan and Co, 1921).Google Scholar
Valéry, Paul, ‘Stendhal’, trans. Turnell, M., in Bloom, Harold (ed.), Stendhal (New York: Chelsea House, 1989), 730.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan, Meaning in Life and Why It Matters (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012).Google Scholar