Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T08:49:35.027Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

False Confessions and Subverted Agency

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 May 2021

Jennifer Lackey*
Affiliation:
Northwestern University

Abstract

In the criminal legal system, confessions have long been considered the ‘gold standard’ in evidence. An immediate problem arises for this gold standard, however, when the prevalence of false confessions is taken into account. In this paper, I take a close look at false confessions in connection with the phenomenon of testimonial injustice. I show that false confessions provide a unique and compelling challenge to the current conceptual tools used to understand this epistemic wrong. In particular, I argue that we cannot make sense of the unjust ways in which false confessions function in our criminal legal system by focusing exclusively on speakers getting less credibility than they deserve. I conclude that the way we conceive of testimonial injustice requires a significant expansion to include what I call agential testimonial injustice – where an unwarranted credibility excess is afforded to speakers when their epistemic agency has been denied or subverted in the obtaining of their testimony.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

The contents of this article were first presented in different form as Jennifer Lackey, ‘False Confessions and Testimonial Injustice,’ 110 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 43–68 (2020).

References

Appleby, Sara C. and Kassin, Saul M., ‘When Self-Report Trumps Science: Effects of Confessions, DNA, and Prosecutorial Theories on Perceptions of Guilt.Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 22 (2016) 127–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert, ‘The Place of Testimony in the Fabric of Knowledge and Justification.American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (1997), 405–22.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, (London: Routledge, 1998).Google Scholar
Bergmann, Michael, ‘Internalism, Externalism and the No-Defeater Condition.Synthese 110 (1997), 399417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, Laurence, ‘Externalist Theories of Epistemic Justification.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1980), 5373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
BonJour, Laurence and Sosa, Ernest, Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues, (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2003).Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler, ‘Content Preservation’, The Philosophical Review, 102 (1993), 457488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. ‘Interlocution, Perception, and Memory’, Philosophical Studies 86 (1997), 2147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick M, Theory of Knowledge, 3rd edn. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1989).Google Scholar
Davis, Emmalon, ‘Typecasts, Tokens, and Spokespersons: A Case for Credibility Excess as Testimonial Injustice’, Hypatia 31 (2016), 485501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, Kristie, ‘Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing.Hypatia 26 (2011), 236–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth, ‘The Epistemology of Testimony.Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 61 (1987), 5783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth. ‘Against Gullibility,’ in Matilal, Bimal Krishna and Chakrabarti, Arindam (eds.), Knowing from Words, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994) 125–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Miranda, Epistemic Injustice: Power & the Ethics of Knowing, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gagarin, Michael, ‘The Torture of Slaves in Athenian Law’, Classical Philology 91 (1996), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaubatz, Kathlyn Taylor, Crime in the Public Mind, (Dearborn: University of Michigan Press, 1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, ‘Should Have Known’, Synthese 194 (2015) 2863–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. I, Epistemology and Cognition, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
Gross, Samuel R., Jacoby, Kristen, Matheson, Daniel J., and Montgomery, Nicholas, ‘Exonerations in the United States 1989 Through 2003.Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 95 (2005) 523–60.Google Scholar
Gudjonsson, Gisli H., and Sigurdssonb, Jon F., ‘The Gudjonsson Questionnaire-Revised (GCQ-R) Factor Structure and its Relationship with Personality’, Personality and Individual Differences 27 (1999) 953–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, David J., ‘Jean Valjean’s Dilemma: The Management of Ex-Convict Identity in the Search for Employment’, Deviant Behavior 24 (2003) 571–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John, Knowledge and Lotteries, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Hieronymi, Pamela, ‘Responsibility for Believing’, Synthese 161 (2008), 357–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschfield, Paul J. and Piquero, Alex R., ‘Normalization and Legitimation: Modeling Stigmatizing Attitudes Toward Ex-OffendersCriminology 48 (2010), 2755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inbau, Fred E., Reid, John E., Buckley, Joseph P., and Jayne, Brian C., Criminal Interrogation and Confessions (4th ed.) (Gaithersberg, MD: Aspen, 2001).Google Scholar
Kasel, Lisa E. and Kassin, Saul M., ‘On the Presumption of Evidentiary Independence: Can Confessions Corrupt Eyewitness Identifications?Psychological Science 20 (2009), 122–26.Google Scholar
Kassin, Saul M., ‘On the Psychology of Confessions: Does Innocence Put Innocents at Risk? American Psychologist 60 (2005), 215–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kassin, Saul M., Drizin, Steven A., Grisso, Thomas, Gudjonsson, Gisli H., Leo, Richard A., and Redlich, Allison D., ‘Police-Induced Confessions: Risk Factors and Recommendations.Law and Human Behavior 34 (2010), 338.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kassin, Saul M., and Kiechel, Katherine L., ‘The Social Psychology of False Confessions:Compliance, Internalization, and Confabulation.Psychological Science 7 (1996), 125–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kassin, Saul M., and McNall, Karlyn, ‘Police Interrogations and Confessions: Communicating Promises and Threats by Pragmatic Implication.Law and Human Behavior 15 (1991), 233–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kassin, Saul M., and Norwick, Rebecca J., ‘Why People Waive Their Miranda Rights: The Power of Innocence.Law and Human Behavior 28 (2004) 211–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kassin, Saul M., and Wrightsman, Lawrence S., ‘Confession Evidence,’ in Kassin, Saul M. and Wrightsman, Lawrence S. (eds.) The Psychology of Evidence and Trial Procedure. (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1985) 6794.Google Scholar
Klaver, Jessica R., Lee, Zina, and Gordon Rose, V., ‘Effects of Personality, Interrogation Techniques and Plausibility in an Experimental False Confession Paradigm.Legal and Criminal Psychology 13 (2008), 7188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, ‘Norms of Assertion.Noûs 41 (2007) 594626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source of Knowledge, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. ‘Lies and Deception: An Unhappy Divorce.Analysis 73 (2013) 236–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. ‘Credibility and the Distribution of Epistemic Goods,’ in McCain, Kevin (ed.), Believing in Accordance with the Evidence: New Essays on Evidentialism, (Springer Publishing, 2018) 145–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. ‘False Confessions and Testimonial Injustice’, Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 110 (2020) 4368.Google Scholar
LeBel, Thomas P., ‘Perceptions of and Responses to Stigma’, Sociology Compass 2 (2008) 409–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leo, Richard A. and Ofshe, Richard J., ‘Consequences of False Confessions: Deprivations of Liberty and Miscarriages of Justice in the Age of Psychological Interrogation.Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 88 (1998) 429–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leydon-Hardy, Lauren, ‘Predatory Grooming and Epistemic Infringement,’ in Lackey, Jennifer (ed.), Applied Epistemology, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Forthcoming).Google Scholar
McDowell, John, ‘Knowledge by Hearsay,’ in Matilal, Bimal Krishna and Chakrabarti, Arindam (eds.), Knowing from Words, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994) 195224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McHugh, Conor, ‘Epistemic Responsibility and Doxastic Agency.Philosophical Issues 23 (2013) 132–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinney, Rachel Ann, ‘Extracted Speech’, Social Theory and Practice, 42 (2016) 258–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marion, Stéphanie B. and Kukucka, Jeff, Collins, Carisa, Kassin, Saul M., and Burke, Tara M., ‘Lost Proof of Innocence: The Impact of Confessions on Alibi Witnesses.Law and Human Behavior 40 (2016) 6571.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Medina, José, ‘The Relevance of Credibility Excess in a Proportional View of Epistemic Injustice: Differential Epistemic Authority and the Social Imaginary. Social Epistemology 25 (2011) 1535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, Charles, ‘White Ignorance,’ in Sullivan, Shannon and Tuana, Nancy (eds.), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2007) 1338.Google Scholar
Moston, Stephen, Stephenson, Geoffrey M., and Williamson, Thomas M., ‘The Effects of Case Characteristics on Suspect Behaviour During Police Questioning.British Journal of Criminology 32 (1992) 2339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, Robert A. and Wade, Kimberly A., ‘Innocent But Proven Guilty: Eliciting Internalized False Confessions Using Doctored-Video EvidenceApplied Cognitive Psychology 23 (2009) 624–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Philosophical Explanations, (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Pager, Devah, Marked: Race, Crime, and Finding Work in an Era of Mass Incarceration, (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pilcher, June J. and Huffcutt, Allen I., ‘Effects of Sleep Deprivation on Performance: A Meta-AnalysisSleep 19 (1996) 318–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Plantinga, Alvin, Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, John, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge, (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1986).Google Scholar
Reed, Baron, ‘Epistemic Circularity Squared? Skepticism about Common Sense’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73 (2006) 186–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reed, Baron. ‘Fallibilism, Epistemic Possibility, and Epistemic Agency.Philosophical Issues 23 (2013) 4069.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taslitz, Andrew E, ‘Wrongly Accused: Is Race a Factor in Convicting the Innocent?Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 4 (2006), 121–33.Google Scholar
Tuerkheimer, Deborah, ‘Incredible Women: Sexual Violence and the Credibility Discount.University of Pennsylvania Law Review 166 (2017) 158.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael, Groundless Belief: An Essay on the Possibility of Epistemology, 2nd edn. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, Jock, The Exclusive Society: Social Exclusion, Crime and Difference in Late Modernity. (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 1999).Google Scholar