Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T00:26:50.490Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PLURAL ANCESTRAL LOGIC AS THE LOGIC OF ARITHMETIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 February 2022

OLIVER TATTON-BROWN*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF BRISTOL

Abstract

Neo-Fregeanism aims to provide a possible route to knowledge of arithmetic via Hume’s principle, but this is of only limited significance if it cannot account for how the vast majority of arithmetic knowledge, accrued by ordinary people, is obtained. I argue that Hume’s principle does not capture what is ordinarily meant by numerical identity, but that we can do much better by buttressing plural logic with plural versions of the ancestral operator, obtaining natural and plausible characterizations of various key arithmetic concepts, including finiteness, equinumerosity and addition and multiplication of cardinality—revealing these to be logical concepts, and obtaining much of ordinary arithmetic knowledge as logical knowledge. Supplementing this with an abstraction principle and a simple axiom of infinity (known either empirically or modally) we obtain a full interpretation of arithmetic.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boolos, G. (1984). To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables). The Journal of Philosophy, 81(8), 430449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, G. (1985). Nominalist Platonism. The Philosophical Review, 94(3), 327344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. P., & Rosen, G. (1997). A Subject with No Object: Strategies for Nominalistic Interpretation of Mathematics. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L., & Avron, A. (2019). The middle ground-ancestral logic. Synthese, 196, 26712693.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, B. (2016). Definitions of numbers and their applications. In Ebert, P. A., & Rossberg, M., editors. Abstractionism: Essays in Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 333347.Google Scholar
Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2004). The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays Towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics (new edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hatisaru, V., & Erbas, A. K. (2017). Mathematical knowledge for teaching the function concept and student learning outcomes. International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, 15(4), 703722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heck, R. K. (2011). Frege’s Theorem. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press (originally published under the name “Richard G. Heck, Jr”).Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. (2001). Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett.Google Scholar
Kleiner, I. (1989). Evolution of the function concept: A brief survey. The College Mathematics Journal, 20(4), 282300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2018). Thin Objects: An Abstractionist Account. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, R. M. (1943). A homogeneous system for formal logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 8(1), 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, R. M. (1949). A note on nominalism and recursive functions. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 2731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oliver, A., & Smiley, T. (2016). Plural Logic (second revised and enlarged edition). Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parsons, C. (2009). Mathematical Thought and Its Objects (first edition). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, P. (2008). Ancestral arithmetic and Isaacson’s thesis. Analysis, 68(297), 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, W. W. (2005). The Provenance of Pure Reason: Essays in the Philosophy of Mathematics and Its History. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions? History and Philosophy of Logic, 7(2), 143154 (the posthumously published text of a 1966 lecture, edited by John Corcoran).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tatton-Brown, O. (2019). Primitive recursion and Isaacson’s thesis. Thought A: Journal of Philosophy, 8(1), 415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. II (2003). Understanding and inference. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 77(1), 249293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2016). Abstraction and epistemic entitlement: On the epistemological status of Hume’s principle. In Ebert, P. A., & Rossberg, M., editors. Abstractionism: Essays in Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 162185.Google Scholar
Yi, B.-U. (2006). The logic and meaning of plurals. Part II. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35(3), 239288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar