Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T12:24:38.302Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How I Almost Solved the Problem of Induction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

John Watkins
Affiliation:
The Centre for the Philosophy of the Natural and Social Sciences The London School of Economics

Extract

At the seventh international congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, held at Salzburg in 1983, I was talking with John Searle when I glanced at my watch and exclaimed, I must run. I'm due to solve the problem of induction at 2.15. ‘Yes,’ he replied, I must go too; I'm due to solve the mind-body problem. I don't know how seriously he meant his remark, but I did actually believe that I had cracked this old problem in the Epilogue of my Science and Scepticism,1 the manuscript of which was then with the publisher. In that book I drew a sharp distinction between the problem which faces a theoretical scientist trying to select, out of several competing theories, the one that best fulfils the aim of science, and the pragmatic problem which faces an applied scientist or practical decision-maker trying to select, out of several competing hypotheses, the one that offers the best guidance. I had what I still regard as a viable solution to the theoreticians problem. It aid that theoreticians should prefer that theory, if there is one, that is the best corroborated; for on a certain non-trivial but uncontroversial assumption about what kinds of test have been made, the best corroborated theory will best satisfy what I claimed to be the optimum aim for science: it will be deeper and wider than its rivals and, moreover, possibly true, given all the reported outcomes of tests in its field. For present purposes we can forget the explications I offered for ‘deeper’ and ‘wider’. As to ‘possibly true’: this reflects the abandonment of hopes (still nursed as recently as 1918 by Moritz Schlick, for example) that science can arrive at theories that are certainly true, or at least have a high probability of being true, or at the very least have had their probability raised by the experimental evidence.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

* Based on a talk given on December 4, 1994 at a conference on ‘The Riddle of Induction’ at the department of Continuing Education, University of OxfordGoogle Scholar

1 John Watkins, Science and Scepticism (Princeton: Princeton University Press/London: Hutchinson, 1984). I presented a somewhat modified version of this putative solution in 'The Pragmatic Problem of Induction', Analysis' 48, January,1988, 1820.Google Scholar

2 John Worrall ‘Why Both Popper and Watkins Fail to Solve the Problem of Induction’, in Dagostino and Jarvie (eds) Freedom and Rationality: Essays in Honor of John Watkins (Dordrecht: Kluwer 1989); p. 277. I replied to this and other criticisms in this volume of my Science and Scepticism in Scientific Rationality and the Problem of Induction: Responses to Criticisms′, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 42, September,1991,343–368.Google Scholar

t2 Colin Howson, ‘The Last Word on Induction?’, Erkenntnis 34, (1991), 7382.Google Scholar

t1 'All male mice have long tails and all female mice have long tails'Google Scholar

t2 'All male mice have long tails and all female mice have notlong detailsGoogle Scholar