Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-tn8tq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-15T13:49:43.410Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Singular Terms and Ontological Seriousness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2022

ARTHUR SCHIPPER*
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF FOREIGN PHILOSOPHY, PEKING UNIVERSITY schipper.philosophy@gmail.com

Abstract

Linguistic ontologists and antilinguistic, ‘serious’ ontologists both accept the inference from ‘Fido is a dog’ to ‘Fido has the property of being a dog’ but disagree about its ontological consequences. In arguing that we are committed to properties on the basis of these transformations, linguistic ontologists employ a neo-Fregean meta-ontological principle, on which the function of singular terms is to refer. To reject this, serious ontologists must defend an alternative. This paper defends an alternative on which the function of singular terms is not generally to refer and on which they are generally ontologically noncommittal. This is the best way to reject linguistic, ‘easy’ arguments for the existence of properties. The account recommends neutralism about quantification (drawing on Barcan Marcus and Meinongianism), coherently bringing together two important yet uncombined meta-ontological movements. Moreover, it employs Ramseyan insights about the transformations to provide a nonreductionist, non-error-theoretic redundancy approach to explicit talk about properties.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am especially grateful to Paul Snowdon for his constant support and valuable comments on this paper. Robert Schipper and the anonymous reviewers provided helpful feedback on the paper. I also thank: Tim Crane, Peter Unger, and Francesco Berto for their support and encouragement; Christian Skirke, Chuang Ye, Julius Schönherr, Arvid Båve, Thomas Schindler, Julian Dodd, and Stacie Friend for helpful discussions on directly related ideas; and audiences at Huaqiao, Sun Yat-sen, and Peking Universities and in London, especially Kevin Lynch, George Hull, and Ivan Ivanov.

References

Armstrong, D. M. (1978a) Nominalism and Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1978b) A Theory of Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1980) ‘Against ‘Ostrich’ Nominalism’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 440–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, J. (2020) A Theory of Truthmaking. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1979) ‘Truth’. In Urmson, J. O. and Warnock, G. J. (eds.), Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 117–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barcan Marcus, R. (1972) ‘Quantification and Ontology’. Noûs, 5, 187202.Google Scholar
Barcan Marcus, R. (1978) ‘Nominalism and the Substitutional Quantifier’. The Monist, 61, 351–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barcan Marcus, R. (1993) Modalities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Båve, A. (2015) ‘A Deflationist Error Theory of Properties’. dialectica, 69, 2359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belnap, N., and Dunn, M.. (1968) ‘The Substitution Interpretation of the Quantifiers’. Noûs, 2, 177–85.Google Scholar
Berto, F. (2013) Existence as a Real Property. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boër, S. (1975) ‘Redmon on “Exists”’. Mind, 84, 263–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, R. (2010) ‘Quantification, Naturalness and Ontology’. In Hazlett, A. (ed.), New Waves in Metaphysics (Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan), 826.Google Scholar
Cameron, R. (2014) ‘On the Lack of Direction in Rayo's The Construction of Logical Space ’. Inquiry, 57, 427–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ceusters, W., and Smith, B.. (2015) ‘Aboutness’. ICBO 2015. http://ncor.buffalo.edu/2015/icbo-aboutness.pdf.Google Scholar
Crane, T. (2001) Elements of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crane, T. (2013) The Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael. (1980) ‘“Ostrich Nominalism” or “Mirage Realism”?’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 433–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyke, H. (2008) Metaphysics and the Representational Fallacy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Eklund, M. (2006) ‘Metaontology’. Philosophical Compass, 1/3, 317–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1989) ‘Platonism for Cheap? Crispin Wright on Frege's Context Principle’. In Fields, Realism, Mathematics and Modality (Oxford: Blackwell), 147–70.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1978) Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawley, K. (2019) ‘Comments on Ontology Made Easy by Amie Thomasson’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99, 229–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (2003) From an Ontological Point of View. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (2006) ‘The Legacy of Linguisticism’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 233–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (2012) The Universe as We Find It. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofweber, T. (2016) Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofweber, T. (2019) ‘Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality’. Mind, 128, 699734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, C. (2004) Kripke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Janssen-Lauret, F. (2015) ‘Meta-Ontology, Naturalism, and the Quine-Barcan Marcus Debate’. In G. Kemp and F. Janessen-Lauret (eds.), Quine and his Place in History (Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan), 146–67.Google Scholar
Janssen-Lauret, F. (2016) ‘Committing to an Individual’. Synthese, 193, 583604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1973) ‘Bob and Carol and Ted and Alice’. In Hintikka, J., Moravcsik, J., and Suppes, P. (eds.), Approaches to Natural Language (Dordrecht: Reidel), 490518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1971) ‘Identity and Necessity’. In Kripke, Philosophical Troubles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 126.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983) ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (2001) ‘Truthmaking and Difference-making’. Noûs, 35, 602–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (2003) ‘Speaking with Shadows’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 103–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (2005) ‘The Particular-Universal Distinction’. Mind, 114, 565614.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (2014) ‘How Truth Depends upon Being’. Analysis, 74, 370–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Charles B. (1980) ‘Substance Substantiated’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B., and Heil, J.. (1999) ‘The Ontological Turn’. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, 3460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinong, A. [1904] (1960) ‘The Theory of Objects’. In Chisholm, R. (ed.), Realism and the Background of Phenomenology (Atascadero: Ridgeview), 76117.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, Alexander. (1978) ‘Events, Processes and States’. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2, 415–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (2001) ‘Metaphysical Realism versus Word Magic’. In Aleksandrowicz, D. and Ruß, H. G. (eds.), Realismus—Disziplin—Interdisziplinarität (Amsterdam: Rodopi), 2954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, Alan. (2009) ‘Pleonastic Platonism’. In Dyke, H. (ed.), From Truth to Reality (London: Routledge), 6684.Google Scholar
Pietroski, P. (2005) ‘Meaning before Truth’. In Preyer, G. and Peter, G. (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon), 255302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. (2000) ‘Objects of Thought’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 494502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. (2016) Towards Non-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1953) From a Logical Point of View. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969) Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1980) ‘Soft Impeachment Disowned’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 450–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1981) Theories and Things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. [1925] (1978) ‘Universals’. In D. H. Mellor (ed.), Foundations (London: Routledge), 17–39.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1927) ‘Facts and Propositions’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 7 (Supplementary), 153–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A. (2002) ‘Word and Objects’. Noûs, 36, 436–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A. (2013) The Construction of Logical Space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A., and Yablo, S. (2001) ‘Nominalism through De-nominalization’. Noûs, 35, 7492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritchie, K. (2016) ‘Can Semantics Guide Ontology?’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94, 2441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Routley, R. (1966) ‘Some Things Do Not Exist’. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 7, 251–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1921) The Analysis of Mind. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. (2005) Reference without Referents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2009) ‘On What Grounds What’. In Chalmers, D., Manley, D., and Wasserman, R. (eds.), Metametaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 347–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1994) ‘The Paradox of Meaning’. Noûs, 28, 279324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1996) ‘Language-Created Language-Independent Entities’. Philosophical Topics, 24, 149–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (2003) The Things We Mean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (2019) ‘Amie Thomasson's Easy Approach to Ontology’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99, 244–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schindler, T. (2021) ‘Deflationary Theories of Properties and their Ontology’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2021.1887302.Google Scholar
Schipper, A. (2018) ‘Aboutness and Negative Truths’. Synthese, 195, 3685–722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, A. (2020) ‘Aboutness and Ontology’. Philosophical Studies, 177, 505–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, A. (2021) ‘Fundamental Truthmakers and Non-fundamental Truths’. Synthese, 198, 3073–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, A. (2022) ‘Ontological Accounting and Aboutness’. Asian Journal of Philosophy, 1, 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. (1958) ‘Proper Names’. Mind, 67, 166–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1963) Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Steinberg, A. (2021) ‘How to Properly Lose Direction’. Synthese, 198, 4229–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1959) Individuals. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2001) ‘Ontological Minimalism’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38, 319–31.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2015) Ontology Made Easy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2016) ‘Easy Ontology and Its Consequences’. In Ostertag, G. (ed.), Meanings and Other Things (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, P. K. [1979a] (2006) ‘There Are No Ordinary Objects’. In Unger, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 335.Google Scholar
Unger, P. K. [1979b] (2006) ‘I Do Not Exist’. In Unger, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1990) Material Beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1998) ‘Meta-ontology’. Erkenntnis, 48, 233–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (2007) ‘On Quantifying into Predicate Position’. In Potter, M. (ed.), Mathematical Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 150–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (1996) ‘How in the World’. Philosophical Topics, 24, 255–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (2000) ‘A Paradox of Existence’. In Everett, A. and Hofweber, T. (eds.), Empty Names Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-Existence (Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications), 275312.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (2014) Aboutness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar