Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T10:52:53.068Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘Humeanism’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2015

GALEN STRAWSON*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS AT AUSTINgstrawson@austin.utexas.edu

Abstract:

In metaphysics, the adjective ‘Humean’ is used to describe positions that deny the existence of any necessary connection or causal influence in concrete reality. This usage has been significantly reinforced by David Lewis's employment of ‘Humean’ in the phrase ‘Humean supervenience’. It is, however, not at all clear that this usage is appropriate. Lewis himself raised a doubt about it.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Author 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ayer, A. J. (1973) The Central Questions of Philosophy. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Broughton, J. (1987) ‘Hume's Ideas about Necessary Connection’. Hume Studies, 13, 217244.Google Scholar
Brown, T. (1818) Inquiry into the Relation of Cause and Effect. London: Henry Bohn.Google Scholar
Burke, E. ([1757] 1990) A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful. Edited by Phillips, A.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craig, E. J. (1987) The Mind of God and the Works of Man. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dixon, T. (2010) ‘Introduction’. In Dixon, T. (ed.), Thomas Brown: Selected Philosophical Writings (Thorverton: Imprint Academic).Google Scholar
Garrett, D. (2009) ‘Hume's Theory of Causation: Realist, Reductionist, or Projectivist?’ In Beebee, H., Menzies, P., and Hitchcock, C. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 7391.Google Scholar
Hume, D. ([1739–40] 1978) A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Selby-Bigge, L. A. and Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. ([1739–40] 2000) A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Norton, D. F. and Norton, M.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. ([1741] 1987) ‘The Sceptic’. In Miller, E. F. (ed.), Essays Moral, Political, and Literary (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund), pp. 159180.Google Scholar
Hume, D. ([1748–51] 1975) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Selby-Bigge, L. A. and Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. ([1748–51] 1999) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Beauchamp, T. L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. (1977) ‘A Causal Theory of Counterfactuals’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 55, 321.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011) Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Strauss, Giroux.Google Scholar
Kail, P. (2007) Projection and Realism in Hume's Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemp Smith, N. (1941) The Philosophy of David Hume. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. (1804) Experimental Inquiry into the Nature and Propagation of Heat. London: Mawman.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986) ‘Introduction.’ In Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), ixxvii.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. ([1994] 1999) ‘Reduction of Mind.’ In Guttenplan, S. (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 412431.Google Scholar
O’Hear, A. (1985) What Philosophy Is: An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. ([1981] 1983) ‘Why There Isn't a Ready-made World’. In Putnam, H. (ed.), Realism and Reason (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 205228.Google Scholar
Priestley, J., and Price, R.. ([1778] 1818) A Free Discussion of the Doctrines of Materialism, and Philosophical Necessity. In Rutt, J. T. (ed.), The Theological and Miscellaneous Works of Joseph Priestley, vol. 4 (London: Printed by George Smallfield), 1121.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (2011) ‘Regularities All the Way Down: Thomas Brown's Philosophy of Causation’. In Allen, K. and Stoneham, T. (eds.), Causation and Modern Philosophy (London: Routledge), 220241.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1927) An Outline of Philosophy. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1989) The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. ([2000] 2008) ‘David Hume: Objects and Power’. In Strawson, G. (ed.), Real Materialism and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 415438.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2014) The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume. Revised edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woolhouse, R. (1988) The Empiricists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, J. P. (1983) The Sceptical Realism of David Hume. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, J. P. (2005) ‘The Scientific Reception of Hume's Theory of Causation: Establishing the Positivist Interpretation in Early Nineteenth-Century Scotland.’ In Jones, P. (ed.), The Reception of David Hume in Europe (London: Thoemmes Continuum), 327347.Google Scholar
Wright, J. P. (2009) Hume's ‘A Treatise of Human Nature’. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar