Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T12:53:15.327Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why the West is Perceived as Being Unworthy of Cooperation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Natural selection generated a natural sense of justice. This natural sense of justice created a set of natural rights; rights humans accorded to each other in virtue of being members of the same tribe. Sharing the responsibility for natural rights between all members of the same tribe allowed humans to take advantage of all opportunities for cooperation. Human rights are the present day political emanation of natural rights. Theoretically, human rights are accorded by all humans to all humans in virtue of being humans; however, the idea that the corresponding responsibility is now shared among all humans is not broadly accepted. The natural sense of justice creates an ambiguity: on the one hand humans consider the nation they belong to as the social system that should guarantee their human rights (and likewise they do not consider themselves as having responsibility for the human rights of inhabitants of other nations); on the other hand, as cooperation between nations intensifies, expectations of global mutual responsibility increase as well.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Yamagishi, T., Horitaa, Y., Takagishia, H., Shinadaa, M., Tanidaa, S., and Cook, K., “The Private Rejection of Unfair Offers and Emotional Commitment,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 106, no. 28 (2009): 1152011523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khan, I., The Unheard Truth: Poverty and Human Rights (New York, London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2009): At 3.Google Scholar
Pogge, T., World Poverty and Human Rights, 2nd ed. (Cambridge and Malden, MA: Polity Press, 2008): At 31.Google Scholar
Negativism about natural morality is not, in my opinion, biological: The science of biology does not support it. Many biologists, however, seem to support it. That is why I believe it should be called biologistical negativism about morality.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R., The Selfish Gene, 2nd ed. (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1989): At 3.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R., The God Delusion (New York: Mariner Books, 2006): At 246.Google Scholar
See Dawkins, , supra note 5, at 4.Google Scholar
Sober, E., From a Biological Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1994): At 24–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
With “genealogical ancestors,” I refer to all individuals who would figure in our common genealogy (if it were possible to elaborate it); I thus mean to exclude our ancestors in the broad sense who do not have descendants in the 21st century, i.e., ancestors whose genes have been filtered out by natural selection.Google Scholar
Hart, H., Essays on Bentham, Jurisprudence and Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982): At 79–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shue, H., Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, 2nd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996): At 13.Google Scholar
Taylor, A, The Divided Ground. Indians, Settlers, and the Northern Borderland of the American Revolution (New York: Alfred A Knopf, 2006).Google Scholar
Id., at 29–30.Google Scholar
Id., at 21.Google Scholar
De Waal, F., Chimpanzee Politics, 25th Anniversary ed. (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Id., at 96.Google Scholar
De Waal, F., Good Natured, The Origins of Right and Wrong in Human and Other Animals (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996): At 140.Google Scholar
Id., at 140.Google Scholar
Id., at 141.Google Scholar
See De Waal, , supra note 15, at 97.Google Scholar
See Taylor, , supra note 12, at 29–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 30.Google Scholar
Id., at 31.Google Scholar
Id., at 17.Google Scholar
Id., at 37.Google Scholar
Id., at 19.Google Scholar
Id., at 20.Google Scholar
Id., at 20.Google Scholar
Dyck, A, Rethinking Rights and Responsibilities, The Moral Bonds of Community (Cleveland: The Pilgrim Press, 1994): At 123.Google Scholar
Donnelly, J., Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 2nd ed. (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2003): At 19.Google Scholar
See Shue, , supra note 11, at 19.Google Scholar
See Pogge, , supra note 3, at 72. Underlining added.Google Scholar
Tudge, C., Neanderthals, Bandits & Farmers, How Agriculture Really Began (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1999): At 29.Google Scholar
Id., at 35–41.Google Scholar
Ziegler, D., Brunn, S., and Williams, J., “World Urban Development,” in Brunn, S., Williams, J., Ziegler, D., eds., Cities of the World, World Regional Urban Development, 3rd ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003): At 21.Google Scholar
Dickson, B., “Public Transcripts Expresses in Theatres of Cruelty: The Royal Graves at Ur in Mesopotamia,” Cambridge Archeological Journal 16, no. 2 (2006): 123144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T., “Human Rights and Human Responsibilities,” in De Greiff, P. and Cronin, C., Global Justice & Transnational Politics (Cambridge: The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 2002): At 159.Google Scholar
International Coalition for the Responsibility to Protect website, available at <http://www.responsibilitytoprotect.org> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
Amnesty International, Human Rights for Human Dignity: A Primer on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (2005), at 22, available at <http://www.amnesty.org/en/library/info/POL34/009/2005> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
Alston, P., “Ships Passing in the Night: The Current State of the Human Rights and Development Debate Seen Through the Lens of the Millennium Development Goals,” Human Rights Quarterly 27, no. 3 (2005): 755829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P., A Darwinian Left (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1999): At 12.Google Scholar
Joyce, R., The Evolution of Morality (Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 2006): At 143–177.Google Scholar
Hauser, M., Moral Minds: How Nature Designed our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong (New York: Harper Collins Publishers, 2006): At 426.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F., The Genealogy of Morals, republication of a standard edition of the 1913 translation by Samuel, H. B. (Mineola: Dover Publications, 1887).Google Scholar
Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge: Belknap, 1999).Google Scholar
See Singer, , supra note 41, at 12.Google Scholar
See Donnelly, , supra note 30, at 17.Google Scholar
The position is often contributed to Maritain himself. Beitz, C., The Idea, of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009): At 21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Hauser, , supra note 43, at xix.Google Scholar
See Singer, , supra note 44, at 41.Google Scholar
Cranston, M., What Are Human Rights? (New York: Taplinger Publishing Co., 1973): At 66.Google Scholar
For an extensive elaboration of “official disrespect,” see Pogge, , supra note 3, at 65–69.Google Scholar
Mahbubani, K., Can Asians Think? Second edition (Singapore: Times Books International, 2002): At 59.Google Scholar
See Shue, , supra note 11, at 19.Google Scholar
Béland, D. and Lacours, A., Nationalism and Social Policy: The Politics of Territorial Solidarity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008): At 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
ILO & WTO, Globalization and Informal Jobs in Developing Countries (Geneva: WTO Publications/ILO Publications, 2009): At 9, available at <http://www.ilo.org/public/english/bureau/inst/download/globalinform.pdf> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
General Assembly of the United Nations, United Nations Millennium Declaration (2000), available at <http://www.undemocracy.com/A-RES-55-2.pdf> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
“Programmes and Projects, National Health Accounts, Updated Country Information (2010),” World Health Organization website, available at <http://www.who.int/nha/country/nha_ratios_and_percapita_levels_2002-2006xls.xls> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
International Coalition for the Responsibility to Protect website, available at <http://www.responsibilitytoprotect.org> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
Obama, B., Remarks by the President at the Acceptance of the Nobel Peace Prize (2009), available at <http://www.white-house.gov/the-press-office/remarks-president-acceptance-nobel-peace-prize> (last visited July 16, 2010).+(last+visited+July+16,+2010).>Google Scholar
Mahbubani, K., Beyond the Age of Innocence: Rebuilding Trust between America and the World (New York: Public Affairs, 2005): At 33.Google Scholar
Gray, L., “Copenhagen Climate Summit: Developing Countries Warn of ‘Absolute Devastation,’” Daily Telegraph, December 9, 2009, available at <http://www.telegraph.co.uk/earth/copenhagen-climate-change-confe/6764877/Copenhagen-climate-summit-developing-countries-warn-of-absolute-devastation.html> (last visited July 14, 2010).Google Scholar
Gostin, L., “Meeting Basic Survival Needs of the World's Least Healthy People: Toward a Framework Convention on Global Health,” Georgetown Law Journal 96, no. 2 (2008): 331392.Google Scholar
See Donnelly, , supra note 30, at 21.Google Scholar
See Dyck, , supra note 29, at 123.Google Scholar
See Gostin, , supra note 63, at 343.Google Scholar
Id., at 344.Google Scholar
See Pogge, , supra note 37, at 165.Google Scholar
Banerjee, A, Hollis, A., and Pogge, T., “The Health Impact Fund: Incentives for Improving Access to Medicines,” The Lancet, 375, no. 9709 (2010): 166169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moellendorf, D., Cosmopolitan Justice (Boulder: Westview Press, 2002): At 49.Google Scholar
Merton, R., “The Matthew Effect in Science,” Science 159, no. 3810 (1968): 5663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milanovic, B., Worlds Apart: Measuring International and Global Inequality (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2005): At 57.Google Scholar
Örücü, E., “The Core of Rights and Freedoms: The Limits of Limits,” in Campbell, T., ed., Human Rights: From Rhetoric to Reality (New York: Blackwell, 1986): 53.Google Scholar
Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General comment 3, “The Nature of States Parties Obligations,” at Paragraph 10 (1990) (underlining in original).Google Scholar
Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General comment 14, “The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health,” at paragraphs 43 and 44 (2000).Google Scholar
Id., at paragraph 45.Google Scholar
Ooms, G. and Hammonds, R., “Correcting Globalisation in Health: Transnational Entitlements versus the Ethical Imperative of Reducing Aid-Dependency,” Public Health Ethics 1, no. 2 (2008): 154170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Gostin, , supra note 63.Google Scholar
Shapiro, I., Containment: Rebuilding a Strategy against Global Terror (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007).Google Scholar