Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-5wvtr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T01:35:05.380Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Toward a Formal Interpretation of Kant's Analogies of Experience

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 June 2015

Johan Blok*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, The Netherlands, j.blok@rug.nl
Get access

Abstract

Very often, the rise of non-Euclidean geometry and Einstein's theory of relativity are seen as the decisive defeat of Kant's theoretical philosophy. Scientific progress seems to render Kant's philosophy obsolete. This view became dominant during the first decades of the twentieth century, when the movement of logical positivism arose. Despite extensive criticism of basic tenets of this movement later in the twentieth century, its view of Kant's philosophy is still common. Although it is not my intention to defend Kant infinitely, I think that this view is rather unsatisfactory and even misleading.

Let us consider the first factor: non-Euclidean geometry. If one reads the first Critique carefully, it becomes clear that the claims of transcendental logic do not imply Euclidean geometry. Kant's notion of space, as explained in the aesthetics chapter, is rather limited: it does neither entail nor presuppose a specific form of geometry (Cf. B37-B57). None of his statements about the form of space is specific enough to imply or support Euclidean geometry. Although Kant uses several examples, Euclidean geometry does not play any systematic role; only the pure form of space is at issue in the aesthetics chapter. In my view, the same holds in the case of Newton's physics: it is neither presupposed nor entailed by Kant's transcendental logic. The justification of Newton's physics requires further specialisation and application of the transcendental framework to empirical concepts like matter and motion. Kant took this step in his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H.E. (1983), Kant's Transcendental Idealism. London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Allison, H.E. (1994, ‘Causality and Causal Laws in Kant: a Critique of Michael Friedman’ in Parrini, P. ed., Kant and Contemporary Epistemology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1966), Philosophical Foundations of Physics. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1994), ‘Kant and the Twentieth Century’ in Parrini, P. ed., Kant and Contemporary Epistemology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1902), Kants gesammelte Schriften: herausgegeben von der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften (formerly Königlichen Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften), in 29 vols. Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter (formerly Georg Reimer).Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1992), The Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant, gen. eds.: Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen W.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1998), Logik-Vorlesung: unveröffentlichte Nachschriften. Hamburg: Meiner.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meier, G.F. (1752), Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre. Halle: Gebauer. Reprinted in Kant's gesammelte Schriften vol. XVI.Google Scholar
Morrison, M. (1998), ‘Community and Coexistence: Kant's Third Analogy of Experience’, Kant-Studien 89: 257277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P.F. (1966), The Bounds of Sense. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Watkins, E. (1997), ‘Kant's Third Analogy of Experience’, Kant-Studien 88: 406441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, E. (1998), ‘The Argumentative Structure of Kant's Metaphysical Foundations’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 36: 567–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar