Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-5wvtr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T13:15:18.891Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reliability, Reasons, and Belief Contexts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

R. Bruce Freed*
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario, London, ON, CanadaN6A 3K7

Extract

Here’s a problem that any reliability theory must face, whether it’s one that holds that beliefs are justified just when they’re products of belief-forming mechanisms with the potential of having good records of yielding true beliefs (as in Goldman 1979 and 1986), or one that holds that a belief meets the standards for knowledge if and only if its causal basis rules out any relevant chance of mistake (as in Dretske 1971 and 1981, and Nozick 1981). The problem is made evident when cast in probabilistic terms. Let r be S’s reason for tokening the true belief that p under conditions c. Then, according to reliabilism (and with a number of other things being equal), Sis justified in believing that p under c iff r makes it sufficiently probable that p, whileS knows that p iff the conditional probability that p on r and c is unity. But how do we specify the belief context c to be counted as epistemically relevant? As urged recently by John Pollock (1984), on the face of it there seems to be no principled reason for excluding mention of the truth value of the proposition believed. As he says, ‘The only obvious way to construct an objective non-epistemic kind of definite probability is to make it conditional on everything that is true [at the belief’s tokening]’ (Pollock 1984, 110); and, as he notes, ‘one feature of the present circumstances is a characterization of the belief as a belief in [p ], and another feature is the truth value of [p]’ (109). But if we allow both the belief token and its truth value membership in the relevant belief context, we then have the hopeless task of explaining how the probability of the token’s being true can be anything but one or zero, one if what is believed is true, and zero if it’s false. This in tum would commit reliabilism to the foolish doctrines that a belief’s truth is sufficient for knowledge, while no false belief is ever even justified. No wonder, then, that Pollock says ‘there is no way to construct an intelligible notion of reliability which does the job required by the reliabilist’ (105). And he is surely right in this: Neither knowledge nor justification can be explained as the chance of a belief’s being true if the relevant belief context is required to mention both the belief tokened and its truth value. We would be engaged in a comparably pointless task were we to try to explain the likelihood of a wager’s being a good bet on a horse race when we had to include among the givens both which horse was picked and its finish, or were we to try to make sense of the assertion that a theory’s predictions have a good chance of being true when both what the theory predicts and its outcome had to be included among the givens. (Quine makes a similar point when he says, ‘If there is no distinguishing between a thing’s disposition to act in a certain way in certain circumstances and the mere fact of its so acting in those circumstances, then whatever the thing may do can be laid to a disposition, by defining the circumstances narrowly enough’ [Quine 1973, 5]. See also Goldman 1979, 12; Goldman 1986, 49-51; and Feldman 1985 for related discussions.)

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Davidson, D.Causal Relations,’ Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967). Reprinted as Essay 7 in the author's Essays on Actions and Events. New York: Oxford University Press 1980.Google Scholar
Dretske, F.Epistemic Operators,’ The Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970) 1007–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F.Conclusive Reasons,’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1971) 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F.The Content of Knowledge,’ in Freed, B. et al., eds., Forms of Representation. Amsterdam: North Holland 1975, 77–93.Google Scholar
Dretske, F.Laws of Nature,’ Philosophy of Science 72 (1977) 793–802.Google Scholar
Dretske, F.Referring to Events,’ in French, P. et al., eds., Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1979, 369–79.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT Press 1981.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. and Enc., B.Causal Theories of Knowledge,’ in French, P. et al., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1984, 517–28.Google Scholar
Feldman, R.Reliability and Justification,’ The Monist 68 (1985) 159–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A.Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology,’ chapter 9 in his Representation. Cambridge: MIT Press 1981.Google Scholar
Goldman, A.Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge,’ Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976) 771–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.What is Justified Belief?’ in Pappas, G. ed., Justification and Knowledge. Dordrecht: Reidel 1979, 1–25.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1986.Google Scholar
Harman, G. Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press 1973.Google Scholar
McGinn, C.The Concept of Knowledge,’ in French, P. et al., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1984, 529–54.Google Scholar
Morillo, C.Epistemic Luck, Naturalistic Epistemology, and the Ecology of Knowledge: Or what the Frog Should Have Told Dretske,’ Philosophical Studies 46 (1984) 109–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H. A.Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search,’ Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 19 (1976) 113–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1981.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. Subjunctive Reasoning. Dordrecht: Reidel 1976.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, J.Reliability and Justified Belief,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (1984) 103–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V.Reply to Chomsky,’ in Davidson, D. and Hintikka, J. eds., Words and Objections. Dordrecht: Reidel 1969, 302–11.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. The Roots of Reference. La Salle: Open Court 1973.Google Scholar
Stampe, D.Verificationism and Causal Accounts of Meaning.’ Forthcoming in >Synthese.Synthese.>Google Scholar
Unger, P.An Analysis of Factual Knowledge,’ The Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968) 157–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar