Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T01:31:12.524Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Possible Explanation of Rousseau's General Will1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2014

Patrick Riley*
Affiliation:
Harvard University

Extract

A “general will” is a philosophical and psychological contradiction in terms; will is a conception understandable, if at all, only in terms of individual actions. The problem cannot be glossed over by attempting to reduce the general will—as did T. H. Green—to a “common ego,” or to an analogical forerunner of Kant's pure practical reason. Why, then, did Rousseau make so unviable an idea the center of his political theory, and why has that idea continued to receive serious attention?

The general will has continued to be taken seriously because it is an attempted (though not explicit) amalgam of two extremely important traditions of political thought, which may be called, roughly, ancient “cohesiveness” and modern “voluntarism.” Political thought since the 17th century has been characterized, among other things, by voluntarism, by an emphasis on the assent of individuals as the standard of political legitimacy. One certainly finds this in many of the most important thinkers between Hobbes and Kant; and even Hegel, while scarcely an “atomistic individualist” or a contractarian, explicitly argued that while “in the states of antiquity the subjective end simply coincided with the state's will,” in modern times “we make claims for private judgment, private willing, and private conscience.” When a political decision is to be made, Hegel continued, “an ‘I will’ must be pronounced by man himself.” This “I will,” he thought, must have an “appropriate objective existence” in the person of a monarch; “in a well-organized monarchy, the objective aspect belongs to law alone, and the monarch's part is merely to set to the law the subjective ‘I will’.” If even Hegel allows this voluntarist turn in his own non-contractarian theory, it goes without saying that all of social contract theory can be seen as the supreme example of voluntaristic ideas.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1970

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This title was adopted not out of modesty, but simply because this article makes certain assumptions which are not universally agreed on. Most importantly, it holds that Rousseau understood “will” not only as a psychological attribute but also as a moral faculty; that there is an implicit metaphysical dimension in Rousseau without which a concept such as “willing” would be incomplete. By treating the concept of volition in psychological rather than in metaphysical terms, however, Mrs. J. N. Shklar, in her persuasive Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1969) is able to make the general will both internally consistent and closely related to Rousseau's individual psychology. That is, by treating individual will as a defense-mechanism, and the general will as a collective defense-mechanism (used largely as a weapon against inequality, whose effects for Shklar are mainly psychologically destructive), she is able to make the general will conceptually plausible. This reading, however, seems to involve a weakening of those (admittedly few) passages in which Rousseau speaks, in a traditional way, of volition as a moral faculty whose endorsement is the source of all moral legitimacy, e.g., “to deprive your will of all freedom is to deprive your actions of all morality” ( Contrat Social, chapter IV). This idea is clearly the foundation of Rousseau's attack on paternalism and on the equation of right and force. It is certainly possible to conceive the “general will one has as a citizen” in a psychological and metaphorical sense, if one imagines this “generality” in terms of factors wholly congruent with psychology: education, public spectacles and games, the authority of the legislator. But this can never show how a will in anything but a psychological sense can be general, simply because the education and authority congruent with psychology are not congruent with a concept of free will and of moral choice. A psychological treatment of volition does in fact hold out the best prospect of a consistent treatment of Rousseau; but it also involves a weakening of the voluntarist and contractarian elements of his philosophy.

References

2 Green, T. H., Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation. (Longmans, Green and Co., London, 1941), pp. 82 ff.Google Scholar

3 Barth, Hans, “Volonté Générale et Volonté Particulière chez J.-J. Rousseau,” in Rousseau et la Philosophie Politique, Annales de Philosophie Politique No. 5, (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1965), pp. 44 ff.Google Scholar

4 Chapman, John, “Political Theory: Logical Structure and Enduring Types,” in L'Idée de Philosophie Politique, Annales de Philosophie Politique No. 6, (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1965), pp. 6569Google Scholar.

5 Hegel, G. W. F., Philosophy of Right, translated Knox, T. M., Oxford University Press, London, 1942, pp. 280, 288289Google Scholar.

6 Plamenatz, John, “Equality of Opportunity,” in Aspects of Human Equality, edited Bryson, L., (Harper and Bros., New York, 1957), pp. 79107Google Scholar.

7 Jouvenel, Bertrand de, Sovereignty, translated by Huntington, J., (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1957), various passagesGoogle Scholar.

8 Leibniz accused Hobbes and Pufendorf of adhering to this view. “To say stat pro ratione voluntas, my will takes the place of reason,” Leibniz observed, “is properly the motto of a tyrant.” He traced this line of thought back to Thrasymachus in the Republic, and urged that Hobbes, “who is noted for his paradoxes, wanted to maintain nearly the same thing as Thrasymachus.” See Leibniz, G. W., Meditation sur la Notion Commune de la Justice, edited Mollat, G., Robolsky, Verlag J. H., Leipzig, 1885, pp. 56 ffGoogle Scholar.

9 See particularly Rousseau, J.-J., Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, translated Cole, G. D. H., (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York, 1950), pp. 172174Google Scholar; Rousseau, J.-J., Gouvernement de Pologne in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, C. E., (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1962), Vol. II, pp. 430, 437438Google Scholar; Rousseau, J.-J., Disease on Inequality, translated Cole, G. D. H., (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York, 1950), pp. 247 ff., 266 ff.Google Scholar; Rousseau, J.-J., Lêttre à M. d'Alembert, critical edition of Fuchs, M., (Librairie Droz, Geneva, 1948) (entire)Google Scholar.

10 See particularly Rousseau, Gouvernement de Pologne, op. cit., chapters II and III; Rousseau, Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, op. cit., pp. 153–158; Rousseau, J.-J., Economie Politique in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 253–254; Rousseau, J.-J., Rome et Sparte, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, op. cit., Vol. I pp. 314–318; Shklar, J. N., “Rousseau's Two Models: Sparta and the Age of Gold,” Political Science Quarterly, Vol. LXXXI (March 1966), 2551CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Rousseau, J.-J., Le Bonheur Public, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, op. cit., vol. I pp. 325–326.

12 Rousseau, J.-J., Le Contrat Social, translated Watkins, F., in Political Writings, (Thomas Nelson and Sons, Edinburgh, 1953), p. 42 (hereafter cited as CS)Google Scholar.

13 Rousseau, Le Bonheur Public, op. cit., p. 326.

14 Ibid.

15 Rousseau, CS, op. cit., p. 58.

16 Ibid.

17 Ibid., P. 42.

18 Rousseau, J.-J., Gouvernement de Pologne, translated F. Watkins, in Political Writings, op. cit., pp. 166–167 (hereafter cited as Pologne).

19 Rousseau, J.-J., Économie Politique, translated Cole, G. D. H., (E. P. Dutton and Co., New York, 1950), p. 308Google Scholar (hereafter cited as Éc. Pol.).

20 Ibid.

21 Rousseau, J.-J., Émile (excerpt), in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. II p. 145Google Scholar.

22 Rousseau, , Pologne, pp. 163165Google Scholar.

23 Rousseau, CS, p. 117.

24 Ibid., p. 8.

25 Rousseau, J.-J.Lettres de la Montague, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. II pp. 199200Google Scholar.

26 Ibid.

27 Rousseau, , Ée. Pol., p. 297Google Scholar.

28 Oakeshott, Michael, Rationalism in Politics, (Methuen and Co., London, 1962), pp. 258 ff.Google Scholar; Oakshott, Michael, Introduction to Hobbes'Leviathan, (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1957), pp. XXXVLGoogle Scholar.

29 Rousseau, J.-J., L'État de Guerre, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. I p. 306Google Scholar.

30 Rousseau, CS, p. 20.

31 Oakeshott, , Rationalism in Politics, p. 261Google Scholar.

32 Rousseau, , L'État de Guerre, p. 307Google Scholar.

33 Oakeshott, , Rationalism in Politics, pp. 249251Google Scholar.

34 Rousseau, , Pologne, pp. 163165Google Scholar.

35 Ibid.

36 Rousseau, , Éc. Pol., pp. 293311Google Scholar.

37 Ibid., pp. 307–309.

38 Rousseau, CS, pp. 37–38.

39 Ibid., p. 37.

40 Ibid., p. 44. Cf. Rousseau, J.-J., Des Lois, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, vol. I p. 331.

41 Ibid. (CS).

42 Ibid.

43 Since, for Rousseau, the pre-social man is a “stupid and limited animal,” and becomes a moral and intelligent being only in society, there is a sense in which man's highest nature (rather than original nature) is social. Cf. Rousseau, J.-J., Lêttre à M. Philopolis, in Political Writings, edited by Vaughan, , vol. I, p. 223Google Scholar.

44 Rousseau, CS, p. 25.

45 Ibid.

46 Ibid., p. 42.

47 Ibid., p. 113.

48 Ibid., pp. 26, 29–30, 38–40.

49 Ibid., p. 32.

50 Ibid., p. 40.

51 Ibid., p. 25.

52 Ibid., p. 38.

53 Ibid., p. 40.

54 Ibid., p. 58.

55 Ibid., p. 29.

56 Rousseau, , Éc. Pol., pp. 307308Google Scholar.

57 Ibid., p. 309.

58 Rousseau, Pologne, chapters II-IV; Rousseau, J.-J.Projet pour la Corse, translated Watkins, F., in Political Writings, p. 300Google Scholar.

59 Rousseau, CS, pp. 40–41.

60 Rousseau, , Ée. Pol., p. 293Google Scholar.

61 Ibid., p. 298.

62 Rousseau, Pologne, chapters II–III; Rousseau, , Rome et Sparte, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. I pp. 314320Google Scholar.

63 Rousseau, J.-J., Histoire des Moeurs, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. I p. 337Google Scholar.

64 Rousseau, , Éc. Pol., pp. 302310Google Scholar.

65 Rousseau, CS, pp. 18–19.

66 Ibid., p. 19.

67 Ibid.

68 Ibid., p. 40.

69 Ibid.

70 Ibid., pp. 53–54.

71 Ibid., p. 57.

72 Ibid., pp. 17–18.

73 Ibid., p. 57.

74 Ibid., pp. 152–155.

75 Ibid., p. 15.

76 Ibid., p. 18.

77 Ibid., p. 33.

78 Ibid., p. 31.

79 Ibid., pp. 117–118.

80 Ibid., p. 20.

81 Cassirer, Ernst, Rousseau, Kant and Goethe, translated Gutmann, Kristeller and Randall, , (Harper Torchbacks, New York, 1963), pp. 30 ff.Google Scholar

82 Rousseau, J.-J., Première Version du Contrat Social, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. I p. 462Google Scholar.

83 Rousseau, J.-J., Jugement sur la Polysynodie, in Political Writings, edited Vaughan, , vol. I p. 421Google Scholar.

84 Rousseau, CS, p. 9.

85 Rousseau, , Éc. Pol., p. 297Google Scholar.

86 Rousseau, J.-J., Emile, translated Foxley, B., (Everyman's Library, J. M. Dent and Sons, London 1911), p. 444Google Scholar.

87 Rousseau, CS, p. 41.