Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pjpqr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-30T14:18:02.288Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Issue of a Science of Politics in Utilitarian Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

Fred Kort
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut

Extract

The contested status of the science of politics has compelled its supporters to pursue their endeavor in an atmosphere of continual apology. The contemporary exponents of scientific aspirations in the realm of political phenomena remain on the defensive as they are confronted with the tenacious persistence of two focal problems: (1) Does the study of politics reveal the potentiality of a science, in view of the immense diversity of human behavior, which appears to be unpredictable and beyond control for the purpose of observation? (2) What would constitute the criteria of a science of politics, provided that the possibility of establishing such a discipline is conceded? In its essential features, this dual issue represents the current manifestation of a controversy which emerged in Utilitarian thought. The parties to the dispute were James Mill, Thomas Babington Macaulay (the only participant who cannot be identified with Utilitarianism), and John Stuart Mill. The respective arguments of the contestants were presented in James Mill's Essay on Government (1828), in Macaulay's article, Mill's Essay on Government (1829), and John Stuart Mill's A System of Logic (1843). Although these works have suffered no neglect in the history of political theory, the controversy which they reveal in their combined context has not commanded as much attention as its pertinence to contemporary problems merits.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1952

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Mill, James, Essay on Government, etc. (London, 1828), p. 9Google Scholar.

2 Ibid., p. 10.

3 Ibid., p. 8.

4 Ibid., p. 13.

5 Ibid., p. 17.

6 Ibid., p. 28.

7 Macaulay, Thomas B., “Mill's Essay on Government”, in Critical and Miscellaneous Essays (New York, 1861), Vol. 5, p. 271Google Scholar.

9 Ibid., p. 277.

10 Ibid., p. 289.

11 Ibid., p. 298.

12 Ibid., p. 290.

13 Ibid., p. 302.

14 See Cohen, Morris R. and Nagel, Ernest, An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method (New York, 1934), p. 278Google Scholar.

15 Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic, 8th ed. (New York, 1895), p. 606Google Scholar.

16 Ibid., p. 607.

17 Loc. cit.

18 The particular devices of experimental inquiry which Mill discussed are the Method of Difference, the Method of Indirect Difference, the Method of Agreement, the Method of Concomitant Variations, and the Method of Residue. Their general definitions are found in A System of Logic, pp. 280–291. Their inapplicability to social sciences was expounded by Mill in op. cit., pp. 610–613.

19 A System of Logic, p. 613.

20 Ibid., p. 616.

21 Ibid., p. 618.

22 Ibid., p. 620.

24 Ibid., p. 633.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.