Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2xdlg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-05T01:28:01.995Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Elements of Democracy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

John D. Lewis
Affiliation:
Oberlin College

Extract

“As for democracy, why should we discuss acknowledged madness?” Today numerous clever writers and some serious students are asking the same question that Alcibiades asked some twenty-three centures ago. Yet at the very time when democracy is attacked from all sides, and when Mussolini can speak of trampling on the putrid corpse of liberty, Mussolini himself has the temerity to proclaim that Italian Fascism is the realization of “true democracy.” The Nazis, speaking through Herr Goebbels, present the National Socialist state as “the most ennobled form of a modern democratic state.” And, not to be outdone, Stalin announces that the Soviet constitution of 1936 is “the only constitution that is democratic to the limit.” Two points, then, appear very clear at the outset. First, a theoretical defense of democracy is made more complicated by the unscrupulous license with which the enemies and critics of democracy use the term; and second, “democracy” as a vague, meaningless symbol still has a propaganda value for those who repudiate or disdain any real meaning that the symbol may have.

It is not my purpose to examine in detail the criticisms of democracy, but rather to indicate which of the numerous criticisms are relevant to a discussion of democracy. What is it that is under attack? Is it the basic assumptions of democratic theory, or the machinery of democratic government, or both? To put such a question means, of course, to reopen the old question: What are the essential elements of democratic theory?

Consent is an essential element of democratic theory, but not a distinguishing element. The important test is not whether a major portion of the adult population accepts or approves a government or its policies, but the manner in which this consent is secured. Both Napoleon I and Napoleon III secured the consent of the French people to their imperial dictatorships, and Hitler secured the formal consent of the German people to his puppet parliament and to his own dictatorship. Schuschnigg was about to secure the consent of the Austrian people to the continuance of a non-Nazi, clerical, native dictatorship, but instead Hitler secured the consent of the Austrian people to a Nazi dictatorship.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 1940

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 In University of Michigan, Philosophical Papers (Ann Arbor, 1888), p. 22.Google Scholar

2 Quoted in Frankfurter, F., The Public and Its Government (New Haven, 1930), p. 149.Google Scholar

3 Quoted by Dodds, H. W., in “Bureaucracy and Representative Government,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science (Jan., 1937), p. 165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation, Sec. 139.

5 On this point, see the sensible reasoning of MacIver, R. M. in Community: A Sociological Study (London, 1917).Google Scholar

6 Cf. Pound, R., The Spirit of the Common Law, pp. 185190.Google Scholar

7 In this Review, Vol. 29, No. 1 (Feb., 1935).

8 Ibid., pp. 12–13.

9 Ibid., p. 14.

10 On this point, see Smith, T. V., “Political Liberty Today,” in this Review, Vol. 31, No. 2 (April, 1937).Google Scholar

11 Cf. Dewey, , “Ethics of Democracy,” p. 8.Google Scholar

12 Reason and Nature, p. 392; reprinted from Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 17 (1919).

13 We or They, pp. 84 ff.

14 Schenck v. U. S., 249 U. S. 47 (1919).

15 In this Review, Vol. 31, Nos. 3–4 (June, Aug., 1937).

16 “No person in the executive civil service shall use his official authority or influence for the purpose of interfering with an election or affecting the results thereof. Persons who by the provisions of these rules are in the competitive classified service, while retaining the right to vote as they please and to express privately their opinions on all political subjects, shall take no active part in political management or in political campaigns.” Civil Service Act and Rules, Statutes, Executive Orders and Regulations, U. S. Civil Service Commission (1936), p. 13. The Hatch Act, Public. No. 252, approved Aug. 2, 1939, prohibited certain practices which had not been specified earlier and extended the prohibition against political activity to all federal employes.

Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.