Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-cjp7w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T21:00:14.084Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Varieties of enthymematic effect in Romans 1–4

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 October 2009

John D. Moores
Affiliation:
University College London
Get access

Summary

The character of the enthymeme. Identifying enthymemes.

There is no other Pauline letter in which inferential argument figures more prominently than it does in Romans. Much of this argument takes the form of immediate deductive inference, where each conclusion is drawn from a single premise. Often these two-part units occur in sequence so that the conclusion of one forms the premise of the next. But conclusions involving two premises also often occur, and the resulting process of mediate deductive inference introduces the argumentative structure which is that of the syllogism. The surface structure of Paul's discourse, however, is not normally syllogistic but enthymematic, the syllogistic argument which underlies his statements remaining only partly expressed, and what is expressed being often expressed obliquely.

‘If God be for us, who can be against us?’ is an oblique way of arguing that given God's support we are invincible. It takes as read the premise that God is invincible. Compare the principle behind Goneril's words to Lear: ‘As you are old and reverend, you should be wise.’ They assume the premise that the old are wise. The illustration was among those used by H. W. B. Joseph, who made a number of extremely important points regarding the enthymeme, which nothing in subsequent developments in logical theory has rendered less valid:

An enthymeme … is not a particular form of argument, but a particular way of stating an argument. The name is given to a syllogism with one premise – or, it may be, the conclusion – suppressed. […]

Type
Chapter
Information
Wrestling with Rationality in Paul
Romans 1-8 in a New Perspective
, pp. 33 - 67
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×