Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T01:44:23.636Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Saccadic chronostasis and the continuity of subjective temporal experience across eye movements

from Part II - Temporal phenomena: perception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 October 2010

Romi Nijhawan
Affiliation:
University of Sussex
Beena Khurana
Affiliation:
University of Sussex
Get access

Summary

Summary

The term “saccadic chronostasis” refers to the subjective temporal lengthening of a visual stimulus perceived following a saccadic eye movement. In this chapter, we discuss our preferred account of the illusion, which posits that the onset of the postsaccadic stimulus is antedated to a moment just prior to movement initiation, and review supporting evidence that illustrates key characteristics of the illusion, including its dependency on saccade extent. We conclude with a brief discussion of other examples of biased time perception that have been linked to saccadic chronostasis.

Introduction

When people make a saccadic eye movement to fixate a new visual target, they overestimate the duration for which that target is perceived (Yarrow et al. 2001). This illusion, which we have called saccadic chronostasis, has been demonstrated using the following basic procedure. Subjects make a saccade to a target that changes form or color during the saccade. They judge the duration of the new target stimulus relative to subsequently presented reference stimuli, and these judgments are used to determine a point of subjective equality (PSE; the point at which the target and reference stimuli are perceived to have identical durations). This procedure is schematized in Fig. 10.1. The same task performed while fixating forms a control. Reduced PSEs in saccadic conditions compared to control fixation conditions are a gauge of the temporal overestimation of the postsaccadic stimulus.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, I., Thilo, K. V., Cowey, A., & Walsh, V. (2005). Chronostasis without voluntary action. Experimental Brain Research 161: 125–132.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Allan, L. G. (1979). The perception of time. Percept Psychophys 26: 340–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, P., & Rothwell, J. C. E. (1997). Illusions of time. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts, 27th Annual Meeting 23: 1119.Google Scholar
Campbell, F. W., & Wurtz, R. H. (1978). Saccadic omission: why we do not see a grey-out during a saccadic eye movement. Vision Res 18: 1297–1303.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Diamond, M. R., Ross, J., & Morrone, M. C. (2000). Extraretinal control of saccadic suppression. J Neurosci 20: 3449–3455.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duhamel, J. R., Colby, C. L., & Goldberg, M. E. (1992). The updating of the representation of visual space in parietal cortex by intended eye movements. Science 255: 90–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fischer, B., & Ramsperger, E. (1984). Human express saccades: extremely short reaction times of goal directed eye movements. Experimental Brain Research 57: 191–195.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grondin, S. (1998). Judgments of the duration of visually marked empty time intervals: linking perceived duration and sensitivity. Percept Psychophys 60: 319–330.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grondin, S., & Rousseau, R. (1991). Judging the relative duration of multimodal short empty time intervals. Percept Psychophys 49: 245–256.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haggard, P., Clark, S., & Kalogeras, J. (2002). Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nat Neurosci 5: 382–385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hellstroem, A. (1985). The time-order error and its relatives: mirrors of cognitive processes in comparing. Psychol Bull 97: 35–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodinott-Hill, I., Thilo, K. V., Cowey, A., & Walsh, V. (2002). Auditory chronostasis: hanging on the telephone. Curr Biol 12: 1779–1781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopp, J. J., & Fuchs, A. F. (2002). Investigating the site of human saccadic adaptation with express and targeting saccades. Experimental Brain Research 144: 538–548.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hunt, A. R., Chapman, C. S., & Kingstone, A. (2008). Taking a long look at action and time perception. J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform 34: 125–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, S. R., Newport, R., Osborne, F., Wakely, R., Smith, D., & Walsh, V. (2005). Saccade-contingent spatial and temporal errors are absent for saccadic head movements. Cortex 41: 205–212.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nakamura, K., & Colby, C. L. (2002). Updating of the visual representation in monkey striate and extrastriate cortex during saccades. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 99: 4026–4031.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Park, J., Schlag-Rey, M., & Schlag, J. (2003). Voluntary action expands perceived duration of its sensory consequence. Experimental Brain Research 149: 527–529.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rose, D., & Summers, J. (1995). Duration illusions in a train of visual stimuli. Perception 24: 1177–1187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, J., Morrone, M. C., Goldberg, M. E., & Burr, D. C. (2001). Changes in visual perception at the time of saccades. Trends Neurosci 24: 113–121.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sasaki, T., Suetomi, D., Nakajima, Y., & ten Hoopen, G. (2002). Time-shrinking, its propagation, and Gestalt principles. Perception and Psychophysics 64: 919–931.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sommer, M. A., & Wurtz, R. H. (2002). A pathway in primate brain for internal monitoring of movements. Science 296: 1480–1482.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Treisman, M., Faulkner, A., Naish, P. L., & Brogan, D. (1990). The internal clock: evidence for a temporal oscillator underlying time perception with some estimates of its characteristic frequency. Perception 19: 705–743.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Umeno, M. M., & Goldberg, M. E. (1997). Spatial processing in the monkey frontal eye field. I. Predictive visual responses. J Neurophysiol 78: 1373–1383.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Walker, M. F., Fitzgibbon, E. J., & Goldberg, M. E. (1995). Neurons in the monkey superior colliculus predict the visual result of impending saccadic eye movements. J Neurophysiol 73: 1988–2003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wearden, J. H., Edwards, H., Fakhri, M., & Percival, A. (1998). Why “sounds are judged longer than lights”: application of a model of the internal clock in humans. Q J Exp Psychol B: Comparative and Physiological Psychology 51: 97–120.Google ScholarPubMed
Yang, Z., & Purves, D. (2003). A statistical explanation of visual space. Nat Neurosci 6: 632–640.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., Haggard, P., Heal, R., Brown, P., & Rothwell, J. C. E. (2001). Illusory perceptions of space and time preserve cross-saccadic perceptual continuity. Nature 414: 302–305.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., Haggard, P., & Rothwell, J. C. (2004a). Action, arousal, and subjective time. Conscious Cogn 13: 373–390.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., Johnson, H., Haggard, P., & Rothwell, J. C. E. (2004b). Consistent chronostasis effects across saccade categories imply a subcortical efferent trigger. J Cogn Neurosci 16: 839–847.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., & Rothwell, J. C. E. (2003). Manual chronostasis: tactile perception precedes physical contact. Curr Biol 13: 1134–1139.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., Whiteley, L., Haggard, P., & Rothwell, J. C. (2006a). Biases in the perceived timing of perisaccadic visual and motor events. Perception and Psychophysics 68: 1217–1226.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarrow, K., Whiteley, L., Rothwell, J. C., & Haggard, P. (2006b). Spatial consequences of bridging the saccadic gap. Vision Res 46: 545–555.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×