Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T12:23:06.866Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Functions of a Curve: Leibniz's Original Notion of Functions and Its Meaning for the Parabola

from The Seventeenth Century

Marlow Anderson
Affiliation:
Colorado College
Victor Katz
Affiliation:
University of the District of Columbia
Robin Wilson
Affiliation:
Open University
Get access

Summary

When the notion of a function evolved in the mathematics of the late seventeenth century, the meaning of the term was quite different from our modern set theoretic definition, and also different from the algebraic notions of the nineteenth century. The main conceptual difference was that curves were thought of as having a primary existence apart from any analysis of their numeric or algebraic properties. Equations did not create curves, curves gave rise to equations. When Descartes published his Geometry [10] in 1637, he derived for the first time the algebraic equations of many curves, but never once did he create a curve by plotting points from an equation. Geometrical methods for drawing each curve were always given first, and then by analyzing the geometrical actions involved in the curve drawing apparatus he would arrive at an equation that related pairs of coordinates (not necessarily at right angles to each other) [20]. Descartes used equations to create a taxonomy of curves [17].

This tradition of seeing curves as the result of geometrical actions continued in the work of Roberval, Pascal, Newton, and Leibniz. Descartes used letters to represent various lengths but did not create any specific system of names. Leibniz, who introduced the term function into mathematics [2], considered six different functions associated with a curve, i.e., line segments or lengths that could be determined from each point on a curve relating it to a given line or axis.

Type
Chapter
Information
Sherlock Holmes in Babylon
And Other Tales of Mathematical History
, pp. 292 - 296
Publisher: Mathematical Association of America
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×