Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-sh8wx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T01:38:05.780Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Methods of reasoning in research

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

E. David Ford
Affiliation:
University of Washington
Get access

Summary

Summary

There is no single method of reasoning that scientists can, or do, follow. We reason in two general ways: deductively, when we use the logic of a theory to make a deduction that we then investigate. If we find the deduction correct then we add additional evidence to the theory – inductively, to extend a theory to explain more, where we consider an idea that applies in one situation will also apply in another.

Deduction follows the rules of propositional logic. In research we can use those rules with axioms and postulates to make predictions that we test. Four rules are particularly valuable:

  1. A conjunction is true if, and only if, all of a series of linked propositions are true.

  2. A disjunction is true if any of a series of linked propositions is true.

  3. Some deductions require that concepts be equivalent, and that must be established by research.

  4. The implication statement has the form, “if p, then q” and sequences of such statements are used to establish chains of scientific reasoning.

While the rules of propositional logic are the base of much scientific reasoning, their use is constrained in ecology by the probabilistic nature of many concepts and the problems of investigating systems with multiple causality.

Much reasoning that ecological scientists use to construct theories is inductive. We argue “If such an event/process/condition (A) occurs, then we will observe a particular result (B).” We investigate to see whether B actually occurs, and if it does then we may conclude that A is true. However, B may not be the result of A but of some other factors overlooked in the investigation.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×