Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-cnmwb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T03:24:57.340Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Conceptual and propositional analysis for defining research problems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

E. David Ford
Affiliation:
University of Washington
Get access

Summary

Summary

Scientific research requires that we place the subjective process of developing new ideas into a logical framework of challenge and questioning through debate and the collection of new data. This is a continuous process (Fig. 3.1), and the iteration between axioms and data is driven forward by four processes – imagination, investigation, comparison, and deduction. These develop knowledge through three states: (1) axioms that already have been researched and refined, (2) postulates that you wish to research, and (3) data statements that describe how data will be collected and used to assess a postulate.

To begin in research you must make a conceptual and propositional analysis. Axioms and postulates must be defined and a description given of the data statements required to examine the postulates. The key to these definitions is a critical analysis of the concepts they use. The component concepts provide a network of connections among axioms and between axioms and postulates. Concepts can be classified according to their status in the function of research, i.e., whether they are well researched, are recently constructed from imagination, or are measurements. Classifying concepts allows you to define and describe your knowledge about the subject you intend to research and what you intend to measure. The way to logical and statistical analysis is then open.

Introduction

The growth of scientific knowledge is sometimes compared to the building of a structure brick by brick. This analogy stresses the progressive nature of science as new investigations are made. But it does not accommodate the reevaluation and change that can take place as we develop scientific understanding.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×