Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-fv566 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T10:27:47.313Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Ayer's first empiricist criterion of meaning: why does it fail?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

David Lewis
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

In the first edition of Language, Truth and Logic, Ayer proposes that ‘the mark of a genuine factual proposition’ is ‘that some experiential propositions can be deduced from it in conjunction with certain other premises without being deducible from those other premises alone’([1], pp. 38–9).

Berlin objects that the criterion is ‘a good deal too liberal’ and admits patent nonsense. His example, near enough, is that the experiential proposition ‘I dislike this logical problem’ can be deduced from the nonsensical ‘this logical problem is green’ in conjunction with the premise ‘I dislike whatever is green’ without being deducible from the latter premise alone ([2], p. 234). Berlin's point is well taken, if indeed a category mistake is nonsense. But it shows at most that the criterion admits too much. We do not yet know how much too much.

In his introduction to the second edition, Ayer accepts Berlin's point in a greatly extended form. Not only does the criterion admit this or that piece of nonsense; it ‘allows meaning to any statement whatsoever. For, given any statement “S” and an observation-statement “O”, “O” follows from “S” and “if S then O” without following from “if S then O” alone’ ([1], p. 11).

Here Ayer goes wrong. For it may very well happen that the consequent of a conditional ‘if S then O’ does follow from that conditional alone. For instance, O follows from ‘if (P or not P) then O’ and from ‘if not O, then O’. Ayer has just overlooked such cases. In general, O follows from ‘if S then O’ just when ‘S or O’ is analytic.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×