Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-08T14:08:34.446Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Genetic epistemology: naturalistic epistemology vs normative epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Richard F. Kitchener
Affiliation:
Colorado State University, USA
Leslie Smith
Affiliation:
Lancaster University
Jacques Vonèche
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Get access

Summary

Introduction: the rise of naturalistic epistemology

The period of the 1960s produced several monumental revolutions in a variety of disciplines. This was true, for example, of the cognitive revolution in which not only did psychology take a cognitive turn, but a new combination of disciplines – the cognitive sciences – also emerged. Although psychologists are well aware of both of these revolutions, there was another revolution that occurred in a sister discipline – philosophy – that has escaped the attention of many psychologists. This was an epistemological revolution – the rise of naturalistic epistemology (NE). (For an introductory survey, see Kitcher, 1992; Maffie, 1990.)

This epistemological movement can correctly be called a revolution because it claimed to be doing epistemology in a new and non-traditional way, one that broke radically and completely with the past. It had its major defenders, most notably Willard Quine (1969), who christened this heretical movement – naturalistic epistemology; but there were several other contemporaries who were making similar claims, e.g. David Armstrong (1973), Paul Churchland (1979), Alvin Goldman (1986), Larry Laudan (1987), etc.; in fact, many individuals claim that John Dewey was one of the first naturalistic epistemologists, whose ancestry can be traced back to nineteenth-century thinkers (e.g. Helmholtz, Mach) and even earlier (e.g. Hume).

Naturalistic epistemology

Although there is no universal agreement among naturalistic epistemologists about all of the basic tenets of NE, there is substantial consensus. I would like to suggest the following as fundamental principles of NE, widely shared by naturalistic epistemologists.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×