Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xm8r8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T01:37:14.454Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nietzsche's Cynicism: Uppercase or lowercase?

from Section 2 - Pre-Socratics and Pythagoreans, Cynics, and Stoics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2013

R. Bracht Branham
Affiliation:
Emory University
Get access

Summary

I cannot exist without the oxygen of laughter.

(Dawn Powell)

And given that even gods philosophize (a conclusion I have been drawn to many times), I do not doubt that they know a new and super-human way of laughing—at the expense of everything serious.

(Nietzsche) (BGE §294)

My purpose here in this article is to sketch an answer to the following question: what did Nietzsche mean when he wrote in Ecce Homo that his books attain here and there “the highest thing that can be attained on earth—Cynicism” (EH Why I Write Such Good Books §3)? At first glance, the idea that ancient Cynicism might be invoked here seems implausible. Were not the dogs, or Cynics, of antiquity the bluntest, crudest, least learned of the ancient schools of philosophy—assuming they can be called a philosophical school, which was doubted even in antiquity? And what survives of the Cynic classics of the fourth and third centuries BCE, aside from a few fragments of Crates and the scurrilous anecdotal traditions preserved in Book 6 of Diogenes Laertius's gossipy Lives and Opinions of Famous Philosophers? What could be here that Nietzsche could sink his canines into? Fortunately (for me), the case for the importance of the Cynics for Nietzsche on every level from literary style to philosophical stance has already been brilliantly made by Heinrich Niehues-Pröbsting. I would like to revisit that case here with a view to supplementing and extending some of its key points by looking at Nietzsche through a Cynic lens, as well as at Cynicism through Nietzsche.

Type
Chapter
Information
Nietzsche and Antiquity
His Reaction and Response to the Classical Tradition
, pp. 170 - 181
Publisher: Boydell & Brewer
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×